Statistiques
| Révision :

root / CSL17 / tech-report / soundness.tex @ 261

Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (17,17 ko)

1
\section{Soundness}
2
\label{sect:soundness}
3
In this section we show that the representable functions of our theories $\arith^i$ are in $\fphi i$ (`soundness').
4
The main result is the following:
5

    
6
\begin{theorem}
7
	\label{thm:soundness}
8
	If $\arith^i$ proves $\forall \vec u^\normal . \forall \vec x^\safe . \exists y^\safe . A(\vec u ; \vec x , y)$ then there is a $\mubci{i-1}$ program $f(\vec u ; \vec x)$ such that $\Nat \models A(\vec u ; \vec x , f(\vec u ; \vec x))$.
9
\end{theorem}
10

    
11

    
12

    
13
The problem for soundness is that we have predicates, for example equality, that take safe arguments in our theory but do not formally satisfy the polychecking lemma for $\mubc$ functions, Lemma~\ref{lem:polychecking}. 
14
For this we will use \emph{length-bounded} witnessing argument, borrowing a similar idea from Bellantoni's work \cite{Bellantoni95}.
15

    
16

    
17
\begin{definition}
18
[Length bounded (in)equality]
19
%We define \emph{length-bounded equality}, $\eq(l;x,y)$ as the characteristic function of the predicate:
20
%\[
21
%x \mode l = y \mode l
22
%\]
23
%which is definable by safe recursion on $l$:
24
%\[
25
%\begin{array}{rcl}
26
%\eq (0 ; x,y) & \dfn & \equivfn (;\bit (0;x),\bit(0;y) ) \\
27
%\eq (\succ i l; x,y) & \dfn & \cond (; \eq ( u;x,y ) , 0, \equivfn (; \bit (\succ i u ; x ) , \bit (\succ i l ; y ))  )
28
%\end{array}
29
%\]
30
We define \emph{length-bounded inequality} as:
31
\[
32
\begin{array}{rcl}
33
\leqfn (0 ; x ,y) & \dfn & \cond(; \bit (0;x), 1, \bit (0;y) ) \\
34
\leqfn (\succ i l ; x,y) & \dfn & \orfn ( ; \cond(;\bit (\succ i l ; x) , \bit(\succ i l ; y),0 ) , \andfn (; \equivfn (\bit (\succ i l ; x) , \bit(\succ i l ; y)) , \leqfn (l;x,y ) ) )
35
\end{array}
36
\]
37
\end{definition}
38

    
39
Notice that $\leqfn (l; x,y) = 1$ just if $x \mode l \leq y \mode l$.
40
We can also define $\eq( l; x,y)$ as $\andfn (;\leq(l;x,y),\leq(l;y,x))$.
41

    
42
%\anupam{Do we need the general form of length-boundedness? E.g. the $*$ functions from Bellantoni's paper? Put above if necessary. Otherwise just add sequence manipulation functions as necessary.}
43
%
44
%Notice that $\eq$ is a polymax bounded polyomial checking function on its normal input, and so can be added to $\mubc$ without problems.
45

    
46

    
47
In the presence of a compatible sorting, we may easily define functions that \emph{evaluate} safe formulae in $\mubc$:
48

    
49

    
50
\begin{proposition}
51
Given a $\Sigma^\safe_i$ formula $A$ and compatible sorting $(\vec u; \vec x)$ of its variables, there is a $\mubci{i}$ program $\charfn{\vec u ;\vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x)$ computing the characteristic function of $A (\vec u \mode l ; \vec x \mode l)$.
52
\end{proposition}
53

    
54
\begin{definition}
55
	[Length bounded characteristic functions]
56
	We define $\mubci{}$ programs $\charfn{}{A} (l , \vec u; \vec x)$, parametrised by a formula $A$ and a compatible typing $(\vec u ; \vec x)$ of its varables, as follows.
57
	%	If $A$ is a $\Pi_{i}$ formula then:
58
	\[
59
	\begin{array}{rcl}
60
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{s\leq t} (l, \vec u ; \vec x) & \dfn & \leqfn(l;s,t) \\
61
	\smallskip
62
	%	\charfn{}{s=t} (l, \vec u ; \vec x) & \dfn & \eq(l;s,t) \\
63
	%	\smallskip
64
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{\neg A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x) & \dfn & \notfn (;\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A}(l , \vec u ; \vec x)) \\
65
	\smallskip
66
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A\cor B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x ) & \dfn & \orfn(; \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w), \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (\vec u ;\vec x) ) \\
67
	\smallskip
68
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A\cand B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x ) & \dfn & \andfn(; \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w), \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (\vec u ;\vec x) )
69
	%	\end{array}
70
	%	\quad
71
	%	\begin{array}{rcl}
72
	\\	\smallskip
73
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{\exists x^\safe . A(x)} (l, \vec u ;\vec x) & \dfn & \begin{cases}
74
	1 & \exists x^\safe . \charfn{}{A(x)} (l, \vec u ;\vec x , x) = 1 \\
75
	0 & \text{otherwise} 
76
	\end{cases} \\
77
	\smallskip
78
	\charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{\forall x^\safe . A(x)} (l, \vec u ;\vec x ) & \dfn & 
79
	\begin{cases}
80
	0 & \exists x^\sigma. \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{ A(x)} (l, \vec u; \vec x , x) = 0 \\
81
	1 & \text{otherwise}
82
	\end{cases}
83
	\end{array}
84
	\]
85
\end{definition}
86

    
87

    
88
We will use the programs $\charfn{}{}$ in the witness functions we define below.
89
Let us write $\charfn{}{i}$ to denote the class of functions $\charfn{}{A}$ for $A \in \Sigma^\safe_{i}$.
90
For the notion of bounding polynomial below we are a little informal with bounds, using `big-oh' notation, since it will suffice just to be `sufficiently large'.
91
Notice that, while we refer to $b_A(l), p(l)$ etc.\ below as a `polynomial', we really mean a \emph{quasipolynomial} (which may also contain $\smsh$), i.e.\ a polynomial in the \emph{length} of $l$, as a slight abuse of notation.
92

    
93

    
94
\begin{definition}
95
	[Length bounded witness function]
96
	For a $\Sigma^\safe_{i}$ formula $A$ with a compatible sorting $(\vec u ; \vec x)$, we define the \emph{length-bounded witness function} $\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w)$ in $\bc (\charfn{}{i-1})$ and its \emph{bounding polynomial} $b_A (l)$ as follows:
97
	\begin{itemize}
98
		\item If $A$ is $\Pi^\safe_{i-1}$ then $\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w) \dfn \charfn{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x )$ and we set $b_A (l) = 1$.
99
		\item If $A$ is $B \cor C$ then we may set $b_A = O(b_B + b_C)$ and define $		\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ;\vec x , w) \dfn		\orfn ( ; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_B (l) , 0 ; w ) ) , \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{C} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_C (l) , 0 ; w ) )  )$.
100
%		\[
101
%		\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ;\vec x , w) 
102
%		\quad \dfn \quad
103
%		\orfn ( ; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_B (l) , 0 ; w ) ) , \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{C} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_C (l) , 0 ; w ) )  )
104
%		\]
105
%		and we may set $b_A = O(b_B + b_C)$.
106
		\item Similarly if $A $ is $B \cand C$, but with $\andfn$ in place of $\orfn$.
107
%		\item If $A$ is $B \cand C$ then
108
%			\[
109
%			\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ;\vec x , w) 
110
%			\quad \dfn \quad
111
%			\andfn ( ; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_B (l) , 0 ; w ) ) , \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{C} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta (b_C (l) , 0 ; w ) )  )
112
%			\]
113
%			and we may set $b_A = O(b_B + b_C)$.
114
		\item If $A$ is $\forall u \leq |t(\vec u;)| . B(u)$ we appeal to sharply bounded closure, Lemma~\ref{lem:sharply-bounded-recursion}, to define
115
		\(
116
		\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A}
117
		 \dfn
118
		\forall u \leq |t|.
119
		\wit{u, \vec u ; \vec x}{B(u)} (l, u, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta( b_{B(t)} (l) , u ; w ) )
120
		\)
121
		%appealing to Lemma~\ref{lem:sharply-bounded-recursion}, 
122
		and 
123
		we set 
124
		$b_A = O(b_{B(t)}^2 )$.
125
		\item Similarly if $A$ is $\exists u^\normal \leq |t(\vec u;)|. A'(u)$, but with $\exists u \leq |t|$ in place of $\forall u \leq |t|$.
126
		\item If $A$ is $\exists x^\safe . B(x) $ then
127
		\(
128
		\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A}
129
		\dfn 
130
		\wit{\vec u ; \vec x , x}{B(x)} ( l, \vec u ; \vec x , \beta( b_{B} (l) , 0;w ) , \beta (q(l) , 1 ;w ))
131
		\)
132
		where $q$ is obtained by the polychecking and bounded minimisation properties, Lemmas~\ref{lem:polychecking} and \ref{lem:bounded-minimisation}, for $\wit{\vec u ; \vec x , x}{B(x)}$.
133
		We may set $b_A = O(b_B + q )$.
134
	\end{itemize}
135
%	\[
136
%	\begin{array}{rcl}
137
%	\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w) & \dfn & \charfn{}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x)  \text{ if $A$ is $\Pi_i$} \\
138
%	\smallskip
139
%	\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A \cor B} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^A , \vec w^B) & \dfn & \cor ( ; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^A) ,\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^B)  )  \\
140
%	\smallskip
141
%	\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A \cand B} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^A , \vec w^B) & \dfn & \cand ( ; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^A) ,\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w^B)  )  \\
142
%	\smallskip
143
%	\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\exists x^\safe . A(x)} (l,\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w , w) & \dfn & \wit{\vec u ; \vec x , x}{A(x)} ( l,\vec u ; \vec x , w , \vec w )
144
%	\\
145
%	\smallskip
146
%	\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\forall u \leq |t(\vec u;)| . A(x)} (l , \vec u ; \vec x, w) & \dfn & 
147
%	\forall u \leq |t(\vec u;)| . \wit{u , \vec u ; \vec x}{A(u)} (l, u , \vec u ; \vec x, \beta(u;w) )
148
%	\end{array}
149
%	\]
150
%	\anupam{need length bounding for sharply bounded quantifiers}
151
\end{definition}
152

    
153

    
154

    
155
\begin{proposition}
156
	\label{prop:wit-rfn}
157
	If, for some $w$, $\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x,w) =1$, then $A (\vec u \mode l ; \vec x \mode l)$ is true.
158
Conversely, if $A (\vec u \mode l ; \vec x \mode l)$ is true then there is some $w \leq b_A(l)$ such that $\wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x,w) =1$.
159
\end{proposition}
160

    
161

    
162
In order to prove Thm.~\ref{thm:soundness} we need the following lemma, essentially giving an interpretation of $\arith^i$ proofs into $\mubci{i-1}$.
163

    
164

    
165
\begin{lemma}
166
		[Proof interpretation]
167
		\label{lem:proof-interp}
168
	From a typed-variable normal form $\arith^i$ proof $\pi$ of a $\Sigma^\safe_i$ sequent $\normal(\vec u), \safe(\vec x) , \Gamma  \seqar \Delta$
169
	there are $\bc (\charfn{}{i-1})$ functions $ f^\pi_B (\vec u ; \vec x , w)$ for $B\in\Delta$ such that
170
	% such that, for any $l, \vec u ; \vec x  , w$, we have:
171
	\[
172
%	\vec a^\nu = \vec u ,
173
%	\vec b^\sigma = \vec u, 
174
%	\bigwedge\limits_{A \in \Gamma} \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{ A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w_A) =1
175
%	\ \implies \
176
%	\bigvee\limits_{B\in \Delta} \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , f^\pi_B((\vec u ; \vec x )\mode l, \vec w \mode p(l))) = 1
177
	\begin{array}{rl}
178
&	\bigwedge\limits_{A \in \Gamma} \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{ A} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w_A \mode b_A(l)) =1 \\
179
\noalign{\medskip}
180
\implies & 	\bigvee\limits_{B\in \Delta} \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{B} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , f^\pi_B((\vec u ; \vec x )\mode l, \vec w \mode p(l))) = 1
181
	\end{array}
182
	\]
183
	for some polynomial $p$.
184
%	\anupam{Need $\vec w \mode p(l)$ for some $p$.}
185
%	\anupam{$l$ may occur freely in the programs $f^\pi_B$}
186
\end{lemma}
187

    
188

    
189

    
190
For the implication above, let us simply refer to the LHS as $\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\Gamma} (l , \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w)$ and the RHS as $\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{ \Delta} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w')$, with $\vec w'$ in place of $\vec f( \cdots )$, which is a slight abuse of notation: we assume that LHS and RHS are clear from context.
191

    
192
\begin{proof}
193
	Since the proof is in typed variable normal form we have that each line of the proof is of the same form, i.e.\ $\normal (\vec u), \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta$ over free variables $\vec u ; \vec x$.
194
	We define the function $f$ inductively, by considering the various final rules of $\pi$.
195
	
196
	
197
	\paragraph*{Negation}
198
	Can assume only on atomic formulae, so no effect.	
199
	
200
	\paragraph*{Logical rules}
201
	Pairing, depairing. Need length-boundedness.
202
	
203
	If we have a left conjunction step:
204
	\[
205
	\vlinf{\lefrul{\cand}}{}{ \normal (\vec u ), \safe (\vec x) , A\cand B , \Gamma \seqar \Delta }{ \normal (\vec u ), \safe (\vec x) , A, B , \Gamma \seqar \Delta}
206
	\]
207
	By inductive hypothesis we have functions $\vec f (\vec u ; \vec x , w_A , w_B , \vec w)$ such that,
208
	\[
209
	\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\Gamma} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , w_A , w_B , \vec w)
210
	\quad \implies \quad
211
	\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\Delta} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \vec f ( (\vec u ; \vec x) \mode l , (w_A , w_B , \vec w) \mode p(l) ))
212
	\]
213
	for some polynomial $p$.
214
	%
215
	We define $\vec f^\pi (\vec u ; \vec x , w , \vec w) \dfn \vec f (\vec u ; \vec x , \beta (p(l),0; w) , \beta(p(l),1;w),\vec w )$ and, by the bounding polynomial for pairing, it suffices to set $p^\pi = O(p)$.
216
	
217
	
218
	Right disjunction step:
219
	\[
220
	\vlinf{\rigrul{\cor}}{}{ \normal (\vec u ), \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta , A \cor B}{ \normal (\vec u ), \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A, B }
221
	\]
222
	$\vec f^\pi_\Delta$ remains the same as that of premiss.
223
	Let $f_A, f_B$ be the functions corresponding to $A$ and $B$ in the premiss, so that:
224
	\[
225
	\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\Gamma} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w)
226
	\quad \implies \quad
227
	\Wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{\Delta} (l, \vec u ; \vec x , f_C ( (\vec u ; \vec x) \mode l , \vec w \mode p(l) ))		
228
	\]
229
	for $C = A,B$ and for some $p$, such that $f_A , f_B$ are bounded by $q(l)$ (again by IH).
230
	We define $f^\pi_{A\cor B} (\vec u ; \vec x, \vec w) \dfn \pair{q(l)}{f_A ((\vec u ; \vec x, \vec w))}{f_B ((\vec u ; \vec x, \vec w))}$.
231
	\paragraph*{Quantifiers}
232
	\anupam{Do $\exists$-right and $\forall$-right, left rules are symmetric.}
233
	
234
	
235
	
236
	Sharply bounded quantifiers are generalised versions of logical rules.
237
	\[
238
	\vlinf{|\forall|}{}{\normal (\vec u) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar  \Delta , \forall u^\normal \leq |t(\vec u;)| . A(u) }{ \normal(u) , \normal (\vec u) , \safe (\vec x) , u \leq |t(\vec u;)| , \Gamma \seqar  \Delta, A(u)  }
239
	\]
240
	By the inductive hypothesis we have functions $\vec f(u , \vec u ; \vec x , w , \vec w)$ such that:
241
	\[
242
	\Wit{u ,\vec u ; \vec x}{\lhs} ( u , \vec u ;\vec x , w , \vec w )
243
	\quad \implies \quad
244
	\Wit{u , \vec u ; \vec x}{\rhs} (u, \vec u ; \vec x , \vec f ((\vec u ; \vec x) \mode l , \vec w \mode p(l) ) )
245
	\]
246
	with $|f|\leq q(|l|)$.
247
	
248
	By Lemma~\ref{lem:sequence-creation}, we have a function $F (l , u , \vec u ; \vec x , w , \vec w) $ such that....
249
	
250
	We set $f^\pi_{\forall u^\normal \leq t . A} (\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w) \dfn F(q(|l|), t(\vec u;), \vec u ; \vec x , 0, \vec w  )$.
251
	
252
	
253
	Right existential:
254
	\[
255
	\vlinf{\rigrul{\exists}}{}{\normal(\vec u ) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta , \exists x . A(x)}{\normal(\vec u ) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta , A(t)}
256
	\]
257
	Here we assume the variables of $t$ are amongst $(\vec u ; \vec x)$, since we are in typed variable normal form.
258
	
259
	
260
	\paragraph*{Contraction}
261
	Left contraction simply duplicates an argument, whereas right contraction requires a conditional on a $\Sigma^\safe_i$ formula.
262
	
263
	\[
264
	\vlinf{\cntr}{}{\normal (\vec u) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta , A }{\normal (\vec u) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma \seqar \Delta , A , A}
265
	\]
266
	
267
	$\vec f^\pi_\Delta$ remains the same as that of premiss. Let $f_0 ,f_1$ correspond to the two copies of $A$ in the premiss.
268
	We define:
269
	\[
270
	f^\pi_A ( \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w  )
271
	\quad \dfn \quad
272
	\cond (; \wit{\vec u ; \vec x}{A} ( l , \vec u ; \vec x , f_0(\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w) ) , f_1(\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w) , f_0(\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w)  )
273
	\]
274
	
275
	
276
	\anupam{For $\normal (\vec u), \safe (\vec x)$ in antecedent, we always consider as a set, so do not display explicitly contraction rules. }
277
	\paragraph*{Induction}
278
	Corresponds to safe recursion on notation.
279
	Suppose final step is (wlog):
280
	\[
281
	\vlinf{\pind}{}{ \normal (\vec u), \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma, A(0) \seqar A(t(\vec u ;)) , \Delta}{ \left\{\normal (u) , \normal (\vec u) , \safe (\vec x) , \Gamma,  A(u) \seqar A(\succ i u ) , \Delta \right\}_{i=0,1} }
282
	\]
283
	\anupam{need to say in normal form part that can assume induction of this form}
284
	For simplicity we will assume $\Delta $ is empty, which we can always do by Prop.~\todo{DO THIS!}
285
	
286
	Now, by the inductive hypothesis, we have functions $h_i$ such that:
287
	\[
288
	\Wit{u , \vec u ; \vec x}{\Gamma, A(0)} (l , u , \vec u ; \vec x ,  \vec w)
289
	\quad \implies \quad
290
	\Wit{u , \vec u ; \vec x}{A(\succ i u)} (l , u , \vec u ; \vec x ,  h_i ((u , \vec u) \mode l ; \vec x \mode l , \vec w) )
291
	\]
292
	First let us define $ f$ as follows:
293
	\[
294
	\begin{array}{rcl}
295
	f (0 , \vec u ; \vec x, \vec w,  w ) & \dfn &  w\\
296
	f( \succ i u , \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w, w) & \dfn & 
297
	h_i (u , \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w , f(u , \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w , w ))
298
	\end{array}
299
	\]
300
	where $\vec w$ corresponds to $\Gamma $ and $w$ corresponds to $A(0)$.
301
	\anupam{Wait, should $\normal (t)$ have a witness? Also there is a problem like Patrick said for formulae like: $\forall x^\safe . \exists y^\safe. (\normal (z) \cor \cnot \normal (z))$, where $z$ is $y$ or otherwise.}
302
	
303
	Now we let $f^\pi (\vec u ; \vec x , \vec w) \dfn f(t(\vec u ; ) , \vec u ; \vec x , \vec w)$.
304
	
305
	\paragraph*{Cut}
306
	If it is a cut on an induction formula, which is safe, then it just corresponds to a safe composition since everything is substituted into a safe position.
307
	Otherwise it is a `raisecut':
308
	\[
309
	\vliinf{\rais\cut}{}{\normal (\vec u ) , \normal (\vec v) , \safe (\vec x) ,\Gamma \seqar \Delta }{ \normal (\vec u) \seqar \exists x^\safe  . A(x) }{ \normal (u)  , \normal (\vec v) , \safe (\vec x) , A(u), \Gamma \seqar \Delta }
310
	\]
311
	In this case we have functions $f(\vec u ; )$ and $\vec g (u, \vec v ; \vec x , w , \vec w )$, in which case we construct $\vec f^\pi$ as:
312
	\[
313
	\vec f^\pi ( \vec u , \vec v ; \vec x , \vec w )
314
	\quad \dfn \quad
315
	\vec g ( \beta (1 ; f(\vec u ;) ) , \vec v ; \vec x , \beta(0;f(\vec u ;)) , \vec w )
316
	\]
317
\end{proof}
318

    
319

    
320

    
321

    
322

    
323

    
324
Now we can prove the soundness result:
325
	
326
	\begin{proof}
327
		[Proof sketch of Thm.~\ref{thm:soundness} from Lemma~\ref{lem:proof-interp}]
328
		Suppose $\arith^i \proves \forall \vec u^\normal . \exists x^\safe . A(\vec u ; x)$. By inversion and Thm.~\ref{thm:normal-form} there is a $\arith^i$ proof $\pi$ of $\normal (\vec u ) \seqar \exists x^\safe. A(\vec u ; x )$ in typed variable normal form.
329
By Lemma~\ref{lem:proof-interp}, we have a $\mubci{i-1}$ function $f^\pi$ with $\wit{\vec u ;}{\exists x^\safe . A} (l, \vec u ; f(\vec u \mode l;)) =1$.
330
By the definition of $\wit{}{}$ and Prop.~\ref{prop:wit-rfn} we have that $\exists x . A(\vec u \mode l; x)$ is true just if $A(\vec u \mode l ; \beta (q(l), 1 ; f(\vec u \mode l;) ))$ is true.
331
Now, since all $\vec u$ are normal, we may simply set $l$ to have a longer length than all of these arguments, so the function $f(\vec u;) \dfn \beta (q(\sum \vec u), 1 ; f(\vec u \mode \sum \vec u;) ))$ suffices to finish the proof.
332
	\end{proof}