Statistiques
| Révision :

root / CSL17 / intro.tex @ 226

Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (17,8 ko)

1 156 adas
\section{Introduction and motivation}
2 154 adas
\label{sect:intro}
3 154 adas
4 156 adas
Today, there are countless approaches towards characterising complexity classes via logic.
5 156 adas
Foremost amongst these lies the proof-theoretic approach, characterising classes as the `representable' functions of some logic or theory.
6 156 adas
Examples include bounded arithmetic \cite{Buss86book} \cite{Krajicek:1996:BAP:225488} \cite{Cook:2010:LFP:1734064}, applicative theories \cite{Cantini02} \cite{KahOit:13:ph-levels}, intrinsic and ramified theories \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories} \cite{BelHof:02}, fragments of linear logic \cite{GirardSS92:bounded-ll} \cite{Girard94:lll} \cite{Lafont04} \cite{Baillot15} and fragments of intuitionistic logic \cite{Leivant94:found-delin-ptime}.
7 156 adas
8 156 adas
To some extent there is a distinction between various notions of `representability', namely between logics that \emph{type} terms computing functions of a given complexity class, and theories that prove the \emph{totality} or \emph{convergence} of programs computing functions in a given complexity class.
9 226 pbaillot
But a perhaps more important distinction is whether the constraints on the logic or theory are
10 226 pbaillot
\textit{explicit} or \textit{implicit}, that is to say whether they stipulate some bounds or resources, or whether the bounds are only \textit{consequence} of some logical properties. One important representative of the first category is \textit{bounded arithmetic}, based on theories of arithmetic where quantiiers are bounded by terms in induction or comprehension formulae \cite{Buss86book,Krajicek:1996:BAP:225488,Cook:2010:LFP:1734064}. Cobham's function algebra  \cite{Cobham}  for polynomial time is of a similar nature, and indeed is used as a tool for the study of bounded arithmetic. In the second category one can range the systems of \textit{implicit computational complexity}, like for instance function algebras based on restrictions of recursion, such as ramified or safe recursion \cite{BellantoniCook92,Leivant95}, arithmetics or logics based on analogous restrictions of induction \cite{Cantini02},  \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories} \cite{BelHof:02},  \cite{Marion01}, \cite{Leivant94:found-delin-ptime} and subsystems of linear logic   \cite{Girard94:lll} \cite{Lafont04} .
11 156 adas
12 219 adas
 Bounded arithmetic is a deep and well-established field, and one of its advantages is its great versatility, allowing a characterization of a wide range of complexity classes, such as $\ptime$, the polynomial hierarchy $\ph$, $\pspace$, $\mathbf{NC}^i$ etc.
13 219 adas
 %It is also closely related to \textit{proof complexity}, the research field investigating the size of propositional proofs in various proof systems. Finally it is also employed for the research direction of \textit{bounded reverse mathematics}.
14 203 pbaillot
15 226 pbaillot
  Implicit computational complexity on the other hand is a slightly more recent and less unified line of research. It aims to relate certain computing disciplines with complexity theoretic features, and has helped shed some light on the foundational nature of `feasibility' (see e.g.~\cite{Leivant94:found-delin-ptime}).
16 226 pbaillot
  Another benefit is that implicit complexity systems can sometimes be extended into techniques for statically controlling the complexity of programs, e.g. in functional or imperative languages (e.g. \cite{Hofmann00,Hofmann03}, \cite{Marion11}).  However the variety of complexity classes that have been characterized in this implicit way is not as large as for bounded arithmetic. In particular implicit complexity has not managed to characterize non-deterministic classes, such as $\mathbf{NP}$ or $\ph$, in a purely logical way.\footnote{Actually some characterizations of such classes do exist, but they either take the form of a function algebra \cite{bellantoni1995fph} or of a type system extended with a non-logical feature \cite{GaboardiMarionRonchi12}.}
17 203 pbaillot
18 219 adas
 Systems in implicit complexity typically imposes constraints on the comprehension scheme, the primitive recursion scheme or the structural rules of proof systems (namely \emph{contraction}).
19 219 adas
% But it seems to us that first-order quantification has not yet been investigated as much as it deserves. We believe that this is one reason of the modest achievements of implicit complexity concerning non-deterministic classes.
20 219 adas
%
21 219 adas
  In the present work we aim to bridge the gap to bounded arithmetic by constructing `implicit' theories that characterise the functional polynomial hierarchy $\fph$ and its levels. We consider a base theory similar to that of bounded arithmetic, but we allow induction on \emph{unbounded} formulae, i.e.\ without any explicit bounds.
22 219 adas
%  By implicit complexity arithmetic we mean that the quantifiers employed should not be bounded quantifiers. Our motivation is to bridge the fields of bounded arithmetic and implicit complexity, and to try pave the way for the design of systems bringing together simplicity (no explicit bounds) and versatility, in which one could transfer some of the main results of bounded arithmetic.
23 219 adas
%
24 219 adas
%  Our methodology will be the following one:
25 219 adas
Naturally another constraint is in order, and for this we will use the concept of \textit{ramification} that is common in implicit complexity \cite{Leivant95,BellantoniCook92}.
26 219 adas
%, adapt it in the setting of first-order arithmetic, and then explore some properties relative to quantification. First
27 219 adas
Also known as \emph{safe recursion}, ramification a discipline which aims at limiting the power of recursion by distinguishing two (or more) levels of integers: the \textit{safe} or level-0 integers (in this work $\safe$), and the \textit{normal} or level-1 ones (in this work $\normal$).
28 219 adas
In a nutshell, recursion is permitted on normal arguments, but recursive calls can only appear in safe positions. Basic operations, such as conditionals and Boolean predicates, can be performed on safe arguments.
29 219 adas
Functions defined in this way correspond to polynomial time functions \cite{BellantoniCook92}.
30 203 pbaillot
31 219 adas
  This discipline can be transposed into first-order arithmetic by adding predicates for normal and safe integers and by limiting the induction scheme by allowing induction only on normal integers, but crucially on formulae with only \emph{safe} unbounded quantifiers.
32 219 adas
  %The key step we make is to focus our attention on \textit{safe quantifiers} that is to say quantifiers on safe variables.
33 219 adas
  These safe quantifiers play a r\^ole analogous to bounded quantifiers in bounded arithmetic. In particular we will consider a hierarchy $\Sigma_i^{\safe}$ of formulas, according to the number of alternations of safe quantifiers, to define a hierarchy of theories $\arith^i$ allowing induction on $\Sigma^\safe_i$ formulae.
34 219 adas
  We show that such a theory proves the totality of precisely the $\fph_i$ functions, relying on a recursion-theoretic characterisation of $\fph$ due to Bellantoni \cite{bellantoni1995fph} to both extract programs and prove completeness of the theory with respect to $\fph_i$.
35 203 pbaillot
36 219 adas
  \medskip
37 219 adas
  \noindent
38 219 adas
  \textbf{Related work}. To the best of our knowledge, our work is the first characterization of the polynomial hierarchy and its levels in an implicit arithmetic. Our approach is however related to several previous works, and differs either by some of the definitions and/or by the complexity class characterized.
39 219 adas
  One particular difference is that we specify programs using arithmetic formulae, as in bounded arithmetic, rather than equational specifications or combinatory terms in other works, which seems to be important for characterizing $\fph$.
40 206 pbaillot
41 219 adas
%   A first axis of classification between the logics and arithmetics for complexity classes is the way by which they specify functions. The options at stake can be enumerated as follows: (i) \textit{formula specification}, as in first-order bounded arithmetic \cite{Buss86book}, (ii) \textit{equational specification}, as in Leivant's intrinsic theories   \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories}, (iii) \textit{combinatory terms} as in applicative theories (e.g. \cite{Strahm03}) or $\lambda$-calculus terms. A second axis, as explained in the introduction, is whether the system is explicit or implicit.
42 219 adas
%
43 219 adas
%   Our approach in this paper is to use the formula-specification point of view, because it is convenient for the polynomial hierarchy.
44 219 adas
   The arithmetic of \cite{KahOit:13:ph-levels} characterizes $\fph$, but it is not implicit, relying on axioms defining bounded schemes.
45 219 adas
%   Some other works are closer to our methodology in the sense that they are implicit arithmetics and rely on a notion of ramification, but they characterize other complexity classes.
46 219 adas
   Leivant's intrinsic theories \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories}  induces characterizations of $\fptime$ and elementary functions, using equational specifications, and \cite{Cantini02} obtains an analogous result for $\fptime$ using combinatory terms.
47 219 adas
   The paper \cite{BelHof:02} also provides a characterization of $\fptime$, with two differences: on the one hand induction is on arbitrarily quantified formulas, and on the other hand the underlying logic is not classical logic but a variant of linear logic, with a modality for normal arguments. Our paper \cite{BaillotDas16} proves a similar result, but with a different method.
48 219 adas
   The lack of contraction is crucial here to stop the theory from exhausting higher complexity classes.
49 219 adas
   Finally the paper \cite{OstrinWainer05} also presents an implicit ramified arithmetic, with quantification on safe variables. Here equational specifications are used instead of formulas and unary integers  instead of binary integers, which leads to a characterization of the elementary functions.
50 206 pbaillot
51 219 adas
  \medskip
52 219 adas
  \noindent
53 219 adas
  \textbf{Outline.} The rest of this paper proceeds as follows. We first give some background on function algebras for $\fptime$ and $\fph$ respectively in Sect.~\ref{sect:prelims}.
54 219 adas
  %Then we describe an encoding of sequences which will be instrumental in the proof of our result.
55 219 adas
  We present our arithmetic theories $\arith^i$ in Sect.~\ref{sect:arithmetic} and prove our soundness result, that the provably total functions of $\arith^i$ are in $\fph_i$, in Sect.~\ref{sect:soundness}. Finally, we prove the completeness result, that all $\fph_i$ functions have a representation provably total in $\arith^i$, in Sect.~\ref{sect:completeness}, and present conclusions in Sect.~\ref{sect:conclusion}.
56 208 pbaillot
57 208 pbaillot
58 206 pbaillot
%  \patrick{
59 206 pbaillot
%  \begin{itemize}
60 206 pbaillot
%  \item our goal: design an unbounded arithmetic for FPH.
61 206 pbaillot
%
62 206 pbaillot
%  motivations: bridge bounded arithmetic and ICC ; enlarge the toolbox of ICC
63 206 pbaillot
%  \item methodology: use ramification, and calibrate the logic by alternance of quantifiers in induction formulas
64 206 pbaillot
%  \item key idea: replace the role of bounded quantifiers by safe quantifiers
65 206 pbaillot
%  \item related works
66 206 pbaillot
%  \end{itemize}
67 206 pbaillot
%  }
68 156 adas
%
69 203 pbaillot
%\anupam{Copied below from DICE submission}
70 156 adas
%
71 203 pbaillot
%Today, there are countless approaches towards characterising complexity classes via logic.
72 203 pbaillot
%Foremost amongst these lies the proof-theoretic approach, characterising classes as the `representable' functions of some logic or theory.
73 203 pbaillot
%Examples include bounded arithmetic \cite{Buss86book} \cite{Krajicek:1996:BAP:225488} \cite{Cook:2010:LFP:1734064}, applicative theories \cite{Cantini02} \cite{KahOit:13:ph-levels}, intrinsic and ramified theories \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories} \cite{BelHof:02}, fragments of linear logic \cite{GirardSS92:bounded-ll} \cite{Girard94:lll} \cite{Lafont04} \cite{Baillot15} and fragments of intuitionistic logic \cite{Leivant94:found-delin-ptime}.
74 203 pbaillot
%
75 203 pbaillot
%To some extent there is a distinction between various notions of `representability', namely between logics that \emph{type} terms computing functions of a given complexity class, and theories that prove the \emph{totality} or \emph{convergence} of programs computing functions in a given complexity class.
76 203 pbaillot
%Perhaps a more important (and somewhat orthogonal) distinction for the \textsc{Dice-Fopara} community is whether the constraints on the logic or theory are \emph{implicit} or \emph{explicit}. The former includes constraints such as ramification, type level and substructural considerations, while the latter includes bounded quantification, bounded modalities etc. This distinction is also naturally exhibited in associated function algebras, e.g. Cobham's \emph{limited} recursion on notation \cite{Cobham} vs.\ Bellantoni and Cook's \emph{predicative} recursion on notation \cite{BellantoniCook92}.
77 203 pbaillot
%
78 203 pbaillot
%Some correlations abound: explicit bounds are typically far more useful for more fine-grained characterisations of complexity classes, e.g.\ levels of the polynomial or arithmetical hierarchies, and often admit witness extraction methods that remain in a ground type programming language, e.g.\ via recursion theoretic characterisations. Implicit bounds, however, are more often associated with higher-typed programming languages, which are arguably more useful for achieving witness extraction at all for powerful theories such as arithmetic and set theory, cf.~\cite{avigad1998godel}, \cite{troelstra1998realizability}. Complexity bounds are harder to obtain, but the framework is nonetheless somewhat more desirable since no bounds occur in the characterisation itself \emph{per se}.
79 203 pbaillot
%
80 203 pbaillot
%In this line of work we attempt to ameliorate the situation by using implicit methods to delineate fine-grained hierarchies of feasible complexity classes, namely the \emph{polynomial hierarchy}, $\ph$.
81 203 pbaillot
%One particular feature of this work that helps make this possible is to break one of the aforementioned correlations: while we use implicit constraints, our witness extraction methods will use only functions of bounded type level. In this way we can naturally appeal to function algebras, which are of ground type in nature, which implicitly characterise $\ph$, namely via \emph{predicative minimisation} \cite{BellantoniThesis}.
82 203 pbaillot
%In order to remain in this class of programs and not get lost with higher types, we appeal to the \emph{witness function method} of extracting programs from proofs, a technique developed by Buss \cite{Buss86book} \cite{Buss:95:wfm-arith}, which is ideal for extracting ground programs directly from classical proofs in weak theories.
83 203 pbaillot
%This extends work presented in \cite{BaillotDas16}. %at \emph{CSL '16}.
84 203 pbaillot
%
85 203 pbaillot
%\subsection{State of the art}
86 203 pbaillot
%As we have already argued, it is natural to expect that characterisations of hierarchies such as $\ph$ are more readily established by using ground or bounded type witness extraction procedures, due to the correspondence between logical searches in a program and the quantification over objects of ground type in a theory.
87 203 pbaillot
%As justification for this position, consider the following table of examples of known characterisations:\footnote{All classes can be taken in their functional variations.}
88 203 pbaillot
%%, distinguished by the type level of programs extracted:
89 203 pbaillot
%
90 203 pbaillot
%\bigskip
91 203 pbaillot
%
92 203 pbaillot
%\begin{tabular}{c|c|c}
93 203 pbaillot
%	Class &	Ground & Higher order\\
94 203 pbaillot
%	\hline
95 203 pbaillot
%	%	quantifiers  & type-level\\
96 203 pbaillot
%	$\nc^i$    & $\mathit{TNC}^i$ \cite{CloTak:1995:nc-ac}, $\mathit{VNC}^i$ \cite{Cook:2010:LFP:1734064} & - \\
97 203 pbaillot
%	$\ptime$  &  $S^1_2$ \cite{Buss86book}, \cite{Strahm03}, $V^1$ \cite{Zambella96} \cite{Cook:2010:LFP:1734064} & $\mathit{LLL}$ \cite{Girard94:lll}, $\mathit{SLL}$ \cite{Lafont04} \\
98 203 pbaillot
%	$\Box_i$  & $S^i_2$ \cite{Buss86book}, \cite{KahOit:13:ph-levels} & -  \\
99 203 pbaillot
%	$\ph$& $S_2$ & - \\
100 203 pbaillot
%	$\pspace$& $U^1_2$ \cite{Buss86book} & $\mathit{STA}_B$ \cite{GaboardiMarionRonchi12} \\
101 203 pbaillot
%	%	$k$-$\exptime$ & -  & $\mathit{ELL}(k)$ \\
102 203 pbaillot
%	Elementary & $I\Delta_0 + \exp$  & $\mathit{ELL}\;  \cite{Girard94:lll}$
103 203 pbaillot
%\end{tabular}
104 203 pbaillot
%
105 203 pbaillot
%\bigskip
106 203 pbaillot
%
107 203 pbaillot
%\noindent
108 203 pbaillot
%Thus, if we want an implicit characterisation of $\ph$ in a logical theory, we should break the apparent (although not universal) link between `implicit' and `higher type'.
109 203 pbaillot
%%If we restrict to the ground setting, where extracted programs do not make use of higher types, we have the following picture.
110 203 pbaillot
%%
111 203 pbaillot
%% Now, if we restrict to the ground setting, where extracted programs do not make use of higher types, there are still several
112 203 pbaillot
%Now, if we zoom in on the ground setting, where extracted programs do not make use of higher types, there are still several parameters by which the characterisations can vary, in particular:
113 203 pbaillot
%\begin{itemize}
114 203 pbaillot
%	\item How are programs specified in the language of the theory? By a formula, as in Peano arithmetic, by a first-order equational program, or by an applicative term in the style of combinatory algebra;
115 203 pbaillot
%	\item What type of programs are extracted from proofs of the theory? A program of a bounded recursion class, e.g.\ of Cobham's algebra, or of a tiered recursion class, e.g.\ of Bellantoni and Cook's algebra.
116 203 pbaillot
%\end{itemize}
117 203 pbaillot
%We classify some known characterisations from the literature according to these two parameters in  the following table:
118 203 pbaillot
%\bigskip
119 203 pbaillot
%
120 203 pbaillot
%\begin{tabular}{c|c|c}
121 156 adas
%	{
122 156 adas
%		%\small model of comp. $\backslash$ extracted program
123 203 pbaillot
%	} & bounded rec. programs & tiered rec. programs \\
124 156 adas
%	\hline &&\\
125 203 pbaillot
%	formula & $\ph$, $\square_i$ (Buss \cite{Buss86book})&\\
126 203 pbaillot
%	%	& bounded induction (Buss \cite{Buss86book}) &\\
127 156 adas
%	\hline &&\\
128 203 pbaillot
%	equational && $\ptime$\\
129 203 pbaillot
%	&& (Leivant \cite{Leivant94:intrinsic-theories}) \\
130 156 adas
%	\hline &&\\
131 203 pbaillot
%	applicative & $\ptime$ (Strahm \cite{Strahm03})  & $\ptime$ \\
132 203 pbaillot
%	&$\ph$ (Kahle-Oitavem \cite{KahOit:13:ph-levels})& (Cantini \cite{Cantini02})
133 156 adas
%\end{tabular}
134 203 pbaillot
%
135 203 pbaillot
%%TODO: improve table to make clear columns and rows, explicit and implicit columns.
136 203 pbaillot
%%
137 203 pbaillot
%%\begin{tabular}{c|c|c|c}
138 203 pbaillot
%%	{
139 203 pbaillot
%%		%\small model of comp. $\backslash$ extracted program
140 203 pbaillot
%%		} & Cobham & mon. constraints & BC-like \\
141 203 pbaillot
%%	\hline &&\\
142 203 pbaillot
%%	formula & PH, $\square_i$&&\\
143 203 pbaillot
%%	& bounded induction (Buss) &&\\
144 203 pbaillot
%%	\hline &&\\
145 203 pbaillot
%%	equational &&& P\\
146 203 pbaillot
%%	&&& (Leivant) \\
147 203 pbaillot
%%	\hline &&\\
148 203 pbaillot
%%	applicative &&PH & P \\
149 203 pbaillot
%%	&&(Kahle-Oitavem)& (Cantini)
150 203 pbaillot
%%\end{tabular}
151 203 pbaillot
%
152 203 pbaillot
%\bigskip
153 203 pbaillot
%
154 203 pbaillot
%\noindent
155 203 pbaillot
%Our goal is to extend the approach using extraction of programs of a tiered recursion class (second column), using the equational style of specification (second row), to the whole of the polynomial hierarchy, i.e.\  $\ph$ and its levels $\square_i$.
156 203 pbaillot
%%Our goal is to extend the implicit approach, via variations of Bellantoni-Cook (BC) programs, to the whole of the polynomial hierarchy.