Statistiques
| Révision :

root / CSL17 / arithmetic.tex @ 225

Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (13,13 ko)

1
\section{An arithmetic for the polynomial hierarchy}\label{sect:arithmetic}
2
%Our base language is $\{ 0, \succ{} , + , \times, \smsh , |\cdot| , \leq \}$. 
3
Our base language consists of constant and function symbols $\{ 0, \succ{} , + , \times, \smsh , |\cdot|, \hlf{}.\}$ and predicate symbols 
4
 $\{\leq, \safe, \normal \}$. The function symbols are interpreted in the intuitive way, with $|x|$ denoting the length of $x$ seen as a binary string, and $\smash(x,y)$ denoting $2^{|x||y|}$, so a string of length $|x||y|+1$.
5
 We may write $\succ{0}(x)$ for $2\cdot x$, $\succ{1}(x)$ for $\succ{}(2\cdot x)$, and $\pred (x)$ for $\hlf{x}$, to better relate to the $\bc$ setting.
6
 
7
We consider formulas of classical first-order logic, over $\neg$, $\cand$, $\cor$, $\forall$, $\exists$, along with usual shorthands and abbreviations. 
8
%The formula $A \cimp B$ will be a notation for $\neg A \cor B$.
9
%We will also use as shorthand notations:
10
%$$ (s=t) = (s\leq t) \cand (t\leq s), \quad (s\neq t) = \neg(s=t).$$ 
11
\textit{Atomic formulas} formulas are of the form $(s\leq t)$, for terms $s,t$.
12
 We will assume, without loss of generality, that formulas are in \textit{De Morgan normal form}, that is to say that in formulas negation can only occur on atomic formulas, and that there is not any occurrence of a subformula of the form $\neg \neg A$.
13
 We write $\exists x^{N_i} . A$ or $\forall x^{N_i} . A$ for $\exists x . (N_i (x) \cand A)$ and $\forall x . (N_i (x) \cimp A)$ respectively.
14

    
15

    
16
The theories we introduce are directly inspired from bounded arithmetic, namely the theories $S^i_2$.
17
We include a similar set of axioms for direct comparison, although in our setting these are not minimal.
18
Indeed, $\#$ can be defined using induction in our setting.
19

    
20
The $\basic$ axioms of bounded arithmetic give the inductive definitions and interrelationships of the various function symbols.
21
It also states the fundamental algebraic properties, i.e.\ $(0,\succ{ } )$ is a free algebra, and, for us, it will also give us certain `typing' information for our function symbols based on their $\bc$ specification, with safe inputs ranging over $\safe$ and normal ones over $\normal$.
22
\begin{definition}
23
	[Basic theory]
24
	The theory $\basic$ consists of the axioms from Appendix \ref{appendix:arithmetic}.
25
	\end{definition}
26

    
27

    
28
Notation: if $\vec t=t_0,\dots, t_k$, we will denote as $\safe(\vec t)$ the sequence of formulas $\safe(t_0),\dots, \safe(t_k)$. Similarly for $\normal(\vec t)$.
29
  
30
\begin{definition}
31
[Derived functions and notations]
32
We write $1,2,3,\dots$ for the terms $\succ{} 0, \succ{} \succ{} 0, \succ{} \succ{} \succ{} 0 \dots$, and frequently omit the $\times$ symbol.
33
We define the functions $\succ 0 x , \succ 1 x$ as $2 x$ and $2x +1$ respectively.
34

    
35
Need $bit$, $\beta$ , $\pair{}{}{}$.
36
\end{definition}
37

    
38
(Here use a variation of S12 with sharply bounded quantifiers and safe quantifiers)
39

    
40
Use base theory + sharply bounded quantifiers.
41

    
42

    
43
\begin{definition}
44
[Quantifier hierarchy]
45
$\Sigma^\safe_0 = \Pi^\safe_0 $ is the set of formulae whose only quantifiers are sharply bounded.
46
We define $\Sigma^\safe_{i+1}$ as the closure of $\Pi^\safe_i $ under $\cor, \cand $, safe existentials and sharply bounded quantifiers.
47
We define $\Pi^\safe_{i+1}$ as the closure of $\Sigma^\safe_i $ under $\cor, \cand $, safe universals and sharply bounded quantifiers.
48
\end{definition}
49

    
50

    
51
\anupam{Collection principles for prenexing? Otherwise need to add closure under sharply bounded quantifiers.}
52
\begin{definition}\label{def:polynomialinduction}
53
[Polynomial induction]
54
The \emph{polynomial induction} axiom schema, $\pind$, consists of the following axioms,
55
\[
56
A(0) 
57
\cimp (\forall x^{\normal} . ( A(x) \cimp A(\succ{0} x) ) )
58
\cimp  (\forall x^{\normal} . ( A(x) \cimp A(\succ{1} x) ) ) 
59
\cimp  \forall x^{\normal} . A(x)
60
\]
61
for each formula $A(x)$.
62

    
63
For a class $\Xi$ of formulae, $\cax{\Xi}{\pind}$ denotes the set of induction axioms when $A(x) \in \Xi$. 
64

    
65
%We write $I\Xi$ to denote the theory consisting of $\basic$ and $\cax{\Xi}{\ind}$.
66
\end{definition}
67

    
68

    
69
\begin{definition}\label{def:ariththeory}
70
Define the theory $\arith^i$ consisting of the following axioms:
71
\begin{itemize}
72
	\item $\basic$;
73
	\item $\cpind{\Sigma^\safe_i } $:
74
\end{itemize}
75
and an inference rule, called $\rais$, for closed formulas $\exists y^\normal . A$:
76
\[
77
 \dfrac{\forall \vec x^\normal . \exists  y^\safe .  A }{ \forall \vec x^\normal .\exists y^\normal . A}
78
\]
79
\end{definition}
80
\patrick{I think in the definition of  $\arith^i$ we should impose that the formulas considered are \textit{integer positive}, that is to say that the only negative occurrences of atoms $\safe(t)$, $\normal(t)$ are those occurring in $\forall^{\safe}$ and $\forall^{\normal}$.  Indeed I don't think this can be just proved to be a consequence of a kind of 'normal form' of proofs, as we had discussed (see sect 4.4)}
81

    
82
\anupam{In induction,for inductive cases, need $u\neq 0$ for $\succ 0$ case.}
83

    
84
It is often useful for us to work with \emph{length-induction}, which is equivalent to polynomial induction and well known from bounded arithmetic:
85
\begin{proposition}
86
	[Length induction]
87
	The axiom schema of formulae,
88
\begin{equation}
89
\label{eqn:lind}
90
	( A(0) \cand \forall x^\normal . (A(x) \cimp A(\succ{} x)) ) \cimp \forall x^\safe. A(|x|)
91
\end{equation}
92
	for formulae $A \in \Sigma^\safe_i$
93
	is equivalent to $\cpind{\Sigma^\safe_i}$.
94
\end{proposition}
95
\begin{proof}
96
	Suppose we have $A(0)$ and $A(a) \cimp A(\succ{} a)$ for each $a \in \normal$.
97
	Then, by $\basic$, we have that $A(|a|) \cimp A(|2a|)$ and $A(|a|) \cimp A(|2a+1|)$ for each $a \in \normal$, whence we may conclude $\forall x. A(|x|)$ by polynomial induction on $A(|x|)$.
98
\end{proof}
99

    
100
Let us refer to the axiom schema in \eqref{eqn:lind} as $\clind{\mathcal C}$, when $A \in \mathcal C$.
101
We will freely use this in place of polynomial induction whenever it is convenient.
102

    
103

    
104

    
105

    
106
\subsection{Graphs of some basic functions}\label{sect:graphsbasicfunctions}
107
%Todo: $+1$,  
108

    
109
We say that a function $f$ is represented by a formula $A_f$ if the arithmetic can prove (in the forthcoming proof system) a formula of the form $\forall ^{\normal} \vec u, \forall ^{\safe} x, \exists^{\safe}! y. A_f$. The variables $\vec u$ and $\vec x$ can respectively be thought of as normal and safe arguments of $f$, and $y$ is the result of $f(\vec u; \vec x)$.
110
 
111
Let us give a few examples of formulas representing basic functions.
112
\begin{itemize}
113
\item Projection $\pi_k^{m,n}$: $\forall^{\normal} u_1, \dots, u_m,  \forall^{\safe} x_{m+1}, \dots, x_{m+n}, \exists^{\safe} y. y=x_k$.
114
\item Successor $\succ{}$: $\forall^{\safe} x, \exists^{\safe} y. y=x+1.$. The formulas for the binary successors $\succ{0}$, $\succ{1}$ and the constant functions $\epsilon^k$ are defined in a similar way.
115
\item Predecessor $p$:   $\forall^{\safe} x, \exists^{\safe} y. (x=\succ{0} y \cor x=\succ{1} y \cor (x=\epsilon \cand y= \epsilon)) .$
116
\item Conditional $C$: 
117
$$\begin{array}{ll}
118
\forall^{\safe} x, y_{\epsilon}, y_0, y_1, \exists^{\safe} y. & ((x=\epsilon)\cand (y=y_{\epsilon})\\
119
                                                                                                   & \cor( \exists^{\safe}z.(x=\succ{0}z) \cand (y=y_0))\\
120
                                                                                                   & \cor( \exists^{\safe}z.(x=\succ{1}z) \cand (y=y_1)))\
121
\end{array}
122
$$
123
\item Addition:
124
$\forall^{\safe} x, y,  \exists^{\safe} z. z=x+y$. 
125
\item Prefix:
126

    
127
  This is a predicate that we will need for technical reasons, in the completeness proof. The predicate $\pref(k,x,y)$ holds if the prefix of string $x$
128
  of length $k$ is $y$. It is defined as:
129
  $$\begin{array}{ll}
130
\exists^{\safe} z, \exists^{\normal} l\leq |x|. & (k+l= |x|\\
131
                                                                                                   & \cand \; |z|=l\\
132
                                                                                                   & \cand \; x=y\smsh(2,l)+z)
133
                                                                                                   \end{array}
134
$$
135
\item The following predicates will also be needed in proofs:
136

    
137
$\zerobit(x,k)$ (resp. $\onebit(x,k)$) holds iff the $k$th bit of $x$ is 0 (resp. 1). The predicate $\zerobit(x,k)$  can be
138
defined by:
139
$$ \exists^{\safe} y.(\pref(k,x,y) \cand C(y,0,1,0)).$$
140
\end{itemize}
141

    
142

    
143

    
144

    
145
\subsection{A sequent calculus presentation}
146

    
147
 We denote sequence as $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ where $\Gamma$, $\Delta$ are multi sets of formulas. The sequent calculus rules are displayed on Fig. \ref{fig:sequentcalculus} in Appendix~\ref{sect:app-sequent-calculus}.
148

    
149
%We consider \emph{systems} of `nonlogical' rules extending this sequent calculus, which we write as follows,
150
% \[
151
% \begin{array}{cc}
152
%    \vlinf{(R)}{}{ \Gamma , \Sigma' \seqar \Delta' , \Pi  }{ \{\Gamma , \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i , \Pi \}_{i \in I} }
153
%\end{array}
154
%\]
155
% where, in each rule $(R)$, $I$ is a finite possibly empty set (indicating the number of premises) and we assume the following conditions and terminology:
156
% \begin{enumerate}
157
% \item In $(R)$ the formulas of $\Sigma', \Delta'$  are called \textit{principal}, those of $\Sigma_i, \Delta_i$ are called \textit{active}, and those of   
158
%$ \Gamma,  \Pi$ are called \textit{context formulas}. 
159
%\item Each rule $(R)$ comes with a list $a_1$, \dots, $a_k$ of eigenvariables such that each $a_j$ appears in exactly one $\Sigma_i, \Delta_i$ (so in some active formulas of exactly one premise)  and does not appear in  $\Sigma', \Delta'$ or $ \Gamma,  \Pi$.
160
%    \item A system $\mathcal{S}$ of rules must be closed under substitutions of free variables by terms (where these substitutions do not contain the eigenvariables $a_j$ in their domain or codomain).  
161
%   \end{enumerate}
162
% 
163
%%The distinction between modal and nonmodal formulae in $(R)$ induces condition 1
164
% Conditions 2 and 3 are standard requirements for nonlogical rules, independently of the logical setting, cf.\ \cite{Beckmann11}. Condition 2 reflects the intuitive idea that, in our nonlogical rules, we often need a notion of \textit{bound} variables in the active formulas (typically for induction rules), for which we rely on eigenvariables. Condition 3 is needed for our proof system to admit elimination of cuts on quantified formulas.
165
%
166
%%\begin{definition}
167
%%[Polynomial induction]
168
%%The \emph{polynomial induction} axiom schema, $\pind$, consists of the following axioms,
169
%%\[
170
%%A(0) 
171
%%\cimp (\forall x^{\normal} . ( A(x) \cimp A(\succ{0} x) ) )
172
%%\cimp  (\forall x^{\normal} . ( A(x) \cimp A(\succ{1} x) ) ) 
173
%%\cimp  \forall x^{\normal} . A(x)
174
%%\]
175
%%for each formula $A(x)$.
176
%%
177
%%For a class $\Xi$ of formulae, $\cax{\Xi}{\pind}$ denotes the set of induction axioms when $A(x) \in \Xi$. 
178
%%
179
%%We write $I\Xi$ to denote the theory consisting of $\basic$ and $\cax{\Xi}{\ind}$.
180
%%\end{definition}
181
%
182
%As an example any axiom can be represented by such a nonlogical rule $(R)$, with no premise ($I=\emptyset$), $\Delta'$ equal to the axiom and $\Gamma=\Sigma'=\Pi$.
183

    
184
We extend the purely logical calculus with certain non-logical rules and initial sequents corresponding to our theories $\arith^i$.
185
 For instance the axiom $\pind$ of Def. \ref{def:polynomialinduction} is represented by the following rule:
186
\begin{equation}
187
\label{eqn:ind-rule}
188
\small
189
\vliinf{\pind}{}{ \normal(t) , \Gamma , A(0) \seqar A(t), \Delta }{ \normal(a) , \Gamma, A(a) \seqar A(\succ{0} a) , \Delta }{ \normal(a) , \Gamma, A(a) \seqar A(\succ{1} a) , \Delta  }
190
\end{equation}
191
where $I=2$ and  in all cases, $t$ varies over arbitrary terms and the eigenvariable $a$ does not occur in the lower sequent of the $\pind$ rule.
192

    
193
Similarly the $\rais$ inference rule of Def. \ref{def:ariththeory} is represented by the nonlogical rule:
194
 \[
195
 \begin{array}{cc}
196
    \vlinf{\rais}{}{  \normal(t_1), \dots, \normal(t_k) \seqar  \exists  y^\normal .  A }{  \normal(t_1), \dots, \normal(t_k) \seqar \exists  y^\safe .  A}
197
\end{array}
198
\]
199

    
200
%\patrick{In fact, I think we rather need the following nonlogical rule, which implies the previous one but is I guess more general:
201
%\[
202
% \begin{array}{cc}
203
%    \vlinf{\rais}{}{  \normal(t_1), \dots, \normal(t_k) \seqar  \normal(t) }{  \normal(t_1), \dots, \normal(t_k) \seqar \safe(t)}
204
%\end{array}
205
%\]
206
%}
207

    
208
The $\basic$ axioms are equivalent to the following nonlogical rules, that we will also designate by $\basic$:
209
\[
210
\small
211
\begin{array}{l}
212
\begin{array}{cccc}
213
\vlinf{}{}{\seqar \safe (0)}{}&
214
\vlinf{}{}{\safe(t) \seqar \safe(\succ{} t)}{}&
215
\vlinf{}{}{ \safe (t)   \seqar 0 \neq \succ{} t}{} &
216
\vlinf{}{}{\safe (s) , \safe (t)  , \succ{} s = \succ{} t\seqar s = t }{}\\
217
\end{array}
218
\\
219
\vlinf{}{}{\safe (t) \seqar t = 0 \cor \exists y^\safe . t = \succ{} y  }{}
220
\qquad
221
\vlinf{}{}{\safe(s), \safe(t) \seqar \safe(s+t) }{}\\
222
\vlinf{}{}{\normal (s), \safe(t) \seqar \safe(s \times t)  }{}
223
\qquad
224
\vlinf{}{}{\normal (s), \normal(t) \seqar \safe(s \smsh t)  }{}\\
225
\vlinf{}{}{\normal(t) \seqar \safe(t)  }{}
226
\end{array}
227
\]
228

    
229
 The sequent calculus for $\arith^i$ is that of Fig. \ref{fig:sequentcalculus} extended with the $\basic$,  $\cpind{\Sigma^\safe_i } $ and $\rais$ nonlogical rules.
230
 
231
\todo{Present typed variable free-cut free form.}
232
\anupam{I cut-and-pasted the rest of this section into appendices to save space. Move things back gradually.}
233

    
234
\begin{theorem}
235
	[Typed variable normal form]
236
	\label{thm:normal-form}
237
\end{theorem}