Révision 222 CSL17/appendix-sequent-calculus.tex
appendix-sequent-calculus.tex (revision 222) | ||
---|---|---|
73 | 73 |
\end{array} |
74 | 74 |
\] |
75 | 75 |
\caption{Sequent calculus rules, where $p$ is atomic, $i \in \{ 1,2 \}$, $t$ is a term and the eigenvariable $a$ does not occur free in $\Gamma$ or $\Delta$.}\label{fig:sequentcalculus} |
76 |
\end{figure} |
|
76 |
\end{figure} |
|
77 |
|
|
78 |
|
|
79 |
|
|
80 |
\begin{lemma} |
|
81 |
For any term $t$, its free variables can be split in two sets $\vec{x}$ and $\vec{y}$ such that the sequent $\normal(\vec x), \safe(\vec y) \seqar \safe(t)$ is provable. |
|
82 |
\end{lemma} |
|
83 |
|
|
84 |
\subsection{Free-cut free normal form of proofs} |
|
85 |
\todo{State theorem, with references (Takeuti, Cook-Nguyen) and present the important corollaries for this work.} |
|
86 |
|
|
87 |
Since our nonlogical rules may have many principal formulae on which cuts may be anchored, we need a slightly more general notion of principality. |
|
88 |
\begin{definition}\label{def:anchoredcut} |
|
89 |
We define the notions of \textit{hereditarily principal formula} and \textit{anchored cut} in a $\system$-proof, for a system $\system$, by mutual induction as follows: |
|
90 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
91 |
\item A formula $A$ in a sequent $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ is \textit{hereditarily principal} for a rule instance (S) if either (i) the sequent is in the conclusion of (S) and $A$ is principal in it, or |
|
92 |
(ii) the sequent is in the conclusion of an anchored cut, the direct ancestor of $A$ in the corresponding premise is hereditarily principal for the rule instance (S), and the rule (S) is nonlogical. |
|
93 |
\item A cut-step is an \textit{anchored cut} if the two occurrences of its cut-formula $A$ in each premise are hereditarily principal for nonlogical steps, or one is hereditarily principal for a nonlogical step and the other one is principal for a logical step. |
|
94 |
\end{itemize} |
|
95 |
A cut which is not anchored will also be called a \textit{free-cut}. |
|
96 |
\end{definition} |
|
97 |
As a consequence of this definition, an anchored cut on a formula $A$ has the following properties: |
|
98 |
\begin{itemize} |
|
99 |
\item At least one of the two premises of the cut has above it a sub-branch of the proof which starts (top-down) with a nonlogical step (R) with $A$ as one of its principal formulas, and then a sequence of anchored cuts in which $A$ is part of the context. |
|
100 |
\item The other premise is either of the same form or is a logical step with principal formula $A$. |
|
101 |
\end{itemize} |
|
102 |
|
|
103 |
Now we have (see \cite{Takeuti87}): |
|
104 |
\begin{theorem} |
|
105 |
[Free-cut elimination]\label{thm:freecutelimination} |
|
106 |
\label{thm:free-cut-elim} |
|
107 |
Given a system $\mathcal{S}$, any $\mathcal{S}$-proof $\pi$ can be transformed into a $\system$-proof $\pi'$ with same end sequent and without any free-cut. |
|
108 |
\end{theorem} |
|
109 |
Now we want to deduce from that theorem a normal form property for proofs of certain formulas. But before that let us define some particular classes of sequents and proofs. |
|
110 |
|
|
111 |
Say that a sequent $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ is \textit{well-typed} if for any free variable $x$ occurring in $\Gamma$ or $\Delta$, there exists a formula $\safe(x)$ or $\normal(x)$ in $\Gamma$. A proof is well-typed if its sequence are. |
|
112 |
|
|
113 |
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:welltyped} |
|
114 |
If a well-typed sequent $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ is provable, then there exists $\vec u$ such that |
|
115 |
the sequent $\normal(\vec u), \Gamma \seqar \Delta$ admits a well-typed proof. |
|
116 |
\end{lemma} |
|
117 |
\patrick{It seems to me the statement had to be modified so as to prove the lemma. Maybe I misunderstand something.} |
|
118 |
\begin{proof}[Proof sketch] |
|
119 |
First by Thm \ref{thm:freecutelimination} we know that $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ admits a proof $\pi$ without any free-cut. Let us then prove that $\pi$ can be transformed in a proof $\pi'$ of conclusion of the form $\normal(\vec u), \Gamma \seqar \Delta$ and such that, for any sequent, if it is well-typed then its premises are well-typed. |
|
120 |
|
|
121 |
Observe first that by definition of $\arith^i$ and the absence of free cut, all quantifiers occurring in a formula of the proof are of one of the forms |
|
122 |
$\forall^{\safe}$, $\exists^{\safe}$, $\forall^{\normal}$, $\exists^{\normal}$, and for the last two ones they are sharply bounded. |
|
123 |
|
|
124 |
Then, one can check that for all rules but the quantifier rules and the cut rule, if the conclusion is well-typed, then so are the two premises. For the remaining rules, $\forall-r$ and $\exists-l$ are unproblematic, because of the observation above. Let us now examine the case of $\exists-r$, with a $\safe$ label, and the other rules can be treated in the same way. In the premise we get a formula $\safe(t) \cand A(t)$. Then what we do is that, if $\vec u$ denote the free variables of $t$, we add to the context of all sequents of the proof $\normal(\vec u)$. We obtain in this way a valid proof new proof, and the premises of the rule have become well-typed. |
|
125 |
\end{proof} |
|
126 |
|
|
127 |
\patrick{As mentioned after Def 14, I don't think that we can prove that the proofs we consider are equivalent to integer positive proofs, by arguing that negative occurrences $\neg \safe(t)$ could be replaced by 'false', by using the lemma above. Indeed even if for all its free variables we have $\safe(\vec x)$, $\normal(\vec u)$ on the l.h.s. of the sequent, it is not clear to me why that would prove $\safe(t)$. My proposition is thus to restrict 'by definition' of $\arith^i$ to integer positive formulas.} |
|
128 |
|
|
129 |
\begin{theorem} |
|
130 |
Assume the $\arith^i$ sequent calculus proves a closed formula $\forall \vec u^\normal . \forall \vec x^\safe . \exists y^\safe . A(\vec u ; \vec x , y)$. Then there exists a proof $\pi$ of the sequent |
|
131 |
$\normal(\vec u), \safe(\vec x) \seqar \exists y^\safe . A(\vec u ; \vec x , y)$ satisfying: |
|
132 |
\begin{enumerate} |
|
133 |
\item $\pi$ only contains $\Sigma^\safe_{i}$ formulas, |
|
134 |
\item $\pi$ is a well-typed and integer-positive proof. |
|
135 |
\end{enumerate} |
|
136 |
\end{theorem} |
Formats disponibles : Unified diff