Statistiques
| Révision :

root / CSL16 / preliminaries.tex @ 203

Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (18,12 ko)

1
\section{Preliminaries}
2
\label{sect:preliminaries}
3
%
4
%\todo{consider removing and just have a section on linear logic, including free-cut elimination.}
5

    
6

    
7
%
8
%
9
%\paragraph*{Notation}
10
%Fix conventions here for use throughout:
11
%\begin{itemize}
12
%\item Eigenvariables: $a, b , c$.
13
%\item (Normal) variables: $u,v,w$. (only when distinction is important, e.g.\ $u^{!\nat}$).
14
%\item (Safe) variables: $x,y,z$. (as above, e.g.\ $x^\nat$.)
15
%\item Terms: $r,s,t$.
16
%\item Formulae: $A,B,C$.
17
%\item Atomic formulae: $p,q$.
18
%\item Free variables in a term, formula, sequent: $FV(u)$, $FV(A)$, $FV(\Gamma)$
19
%\item Sequents: $\Gamma, \Delta, \Sigma, \Pi$.
20
%\item lists of formulas $A(\vec{x})$, $!A(\vec{x})$ (in particular for $A=N$).
21
%\item Proofs: $\pi, \rho, \sigma$.
22
%\item Theories: $\mathcal T$. Sequent systems: $\mathcal S$.
23
%\end{itemize}
24
%
25
%\subsection{Linear logic}
26

    
27
%\anupam{use a system that is already in De Morgan form, for simplicity.}
28
%\anupam{Have skipped units, can reconsider this when in arithmetic. Also in affine setting can be recovered by any contradiction/tautology.}
29

    
30
We formulate linear logic without units with usual notation for the multiplicatives, additives and exponentials from \cite{Girard87}. We restrict negation to the atoms, so that formulae are always in De Morgan normal form, 
31
%and this is reflected in the sequent system below. We have included 
32
and we also consider
33
rules for arbitrary weakening when working in affine settings.
34

    
35
%\anupam{positive and negative.}
36

    
37

    
38

    
39

    
40

    
41
\begin{definition}
42
%[Sequent calculus for linear logic]
43
%[Sequent calculus for affine linear logic]
44
\label{def:LLsequentcalculus}
45
The sequent calculus for (affine) linear logic is as follows:\footnote{We consider a two-sided system since it is more intuitive for certain nonlogical rules, e.g.\ induction, and also convenient for the witness function method we use in Sect.~\ref{sect:wfm}.}
46
\[
47
\small
48
\begin{array}{l}
49
\begin{array}{cccc}
50
\vlinf{\lefrul{\bot}}{}{p, \lnot{p} \seqar }{}
51
& \vlinf{\id}{}{p \seqar p}{}
52
& \vlinf{\rigrul{\bot}}{}{\seqar p, \lnot{p}}{}
53
& \vliinf{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A }{\Sigma, A \seqar \Pi}
54
\\
55
\noalign{\bigskip}
56
%\text{Multiplicatives:} & & & \\
57
%\noalign{\bigskip}
58
\vliinf{\lefrul{\lor}}{}{\Gamma,\Sigma, A \lor B \seqar \Delta, \Pi}{\Gamma, A \seqar \Delta}{\Sigma , B \seqar \Pi}
59
&
60
\vlinf{\lefrul{\land}}{}{\Gamma, A\land B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A , B \seqar \Delta}
61
&
62
\vlinf{\rigrul{\lor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A \lor B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A, B}
63
&
64
\vliinf{\rigrul{\land}}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi , A \land B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta , A}{\Sigma \seqar \Pi , B}
65
\\
66
\noalign{\bigskip}
67
%\text{Additives:} & & & \\
68
%\noalign{\bigskip}
69
\vliinf{\lefrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma, A \laor B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma , A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, B \seqar \Delta}
70
&
71
\vlinf{\lefrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma, A_1\laand A_2 \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A_i \seqar \Delta}
72
&
73
%\vlinf{\lefrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma, A\laand B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, B \seqar \Delta}
74
%\quad
75
\vlinf{\rigrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A_1\laor A_2}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A_i}
76
&
77
%\vlinf{\rigrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A\laor B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, B}
78
%\quad
79
\vliinf{\rigrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A \laand B }{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, B}
80
\\
81
\noalign{\bigskip}
82
%\text{Exponentials:} & & & \\
83
%\noalign{\bigskip}
84
\vlinf{\lefrul{?}}{}{!\Gamma, ?A \seqar ?\Delta}{!\Gamma , A \seqar ?\Delta}
85
&
86
\vlinf{\lefrul{!}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A \seqar \Delta}
87
&
88
\vlinf{\rigrul{?}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A}
89
&
90
\vlinf{\rigrul{!}}{}{!\Gamma \seqar ?\Delta, !A}{!\Gamma \seqar ?\Delta, A}
91
\\
92
\noalign{\bigskip}
93
%\text{Structural:} & & & \\
94
%\noalign{\bigskip}
95

    
96
%\vlinf{\lefrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta}  %% linear logic weakening
97
\vlinf{\lefrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma, A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta}
98
&
99
\vlinf{\lefrul{\cntr}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, !A, !A \seqar \Delta}
100
&
101
%\vlinf{\rigrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A }{\Gamma \seqar \Delta}   %% linear logic weakening
102

    
103
\vlinf{\rigrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A }{\Gamma \seqar \Delta}
104
&
105
\vlinf{\rigrul{\cntr}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A, ?A}
106
\\
107
\noalign{\bigskip}
108
\vlinf{\lefrul{\exists}}{}{\Gamma, \exists x . A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A(a) \seqar \Delta}
109
&
110
\vlinf{\lefrul{\forall}}{}{\Gamma, \forall x. A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A(t) \seqar \Delta}
111
&
112
\vlinf{\rigrul{\exists}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, \exists x . A(x)}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A(t)}
113
&
114
\vlinf{\rigrul{\forall}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, \forall x . A(x)}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A(a) } \\
115
%\noalign{\bigskip}
116
% \vliinf{mix}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta}{\Sigma \seqar \Pi} &&&
117
\end{array}
118
\end{array}
119
\]
120
where $p$ is atomic, $i \in \{ 1,2 \}$, $t$ is a term and the eigenvariable $a$ does not occur free in $\Gamma$ or $\Delta$.
121
\end{definition}
122
%\todo{$\limp$ abbreviation for ...}
123
%\todo{bracketing}
124

    
125
We do not formally include a symbol for implication but we sometimes write $A \limp B$ as shorthand for $\lnot{A} \lor B$, where $\lnot A$ is the De Morgan dual of $A$. We often omit brackets under associativity, and when writing long implications we assume the right-most bracketing.
126

    
127
We will use standard terminology to track formulae in proofs, as presented in e.g.\ \cite{Buss98:intro-proof-theory}.
128
In particular, each rule has a distinguished \textit{principal formula}, e.g.\
129
  $A \lor B$ in the rule $\lefrul{\lor}$ (and similarly for all rules for the binary connectives) and $?A$ in the rule $\rigrul{\cntr}$, and \emph{active formulae}, e.g.\ $A$ and $B$ in $\lefrul{\lor}$ and so on. These induce the notions of (direct) descendants and ancestors in proofs, as in \cite{Buss98:intro-proof-theory}.
130
%The  \textit{direct ancestor} relation on occurrences of formulas in a proof is defined to keep track of identity of formulas from line to line, in the usual way.
131
  
132
       
133
  % Observe that we do not consider here any exchange rules, the sequence are made of multisets of formulas and exchanges are implicit. Note that this system is \textit{affine} in the sense that it includes general weakening rules $\rigrul{\wk}$ and  $\lefrul{\wk}$, while in linear logic   $\rigrul{\wk}$ (resp. $\lefrul{\wk}$) is restricted to formulas of the form $?A$ (resp. $!A$).   In the following though, by linear logic we will mean affine linear logic.
134
  \subsection{Theories and systems}
135
  
136
%  \anupam{need to add a note on semantics}
137
%  \anupam{mention equality rules}
138
%  \anupam{mention equality axioms and first-order theories and models at some point.}
139
  
140
 A \emph{language} is a set of nonlogical symbols (i.e.\ constants, functions, predicates) and a \emph{theory} is a set of closed formulae over some language. We assume that all theories contain the axioms of equality:
141
% \[
142
% \begin{array}{rl}
143
%\refl & \forall x . x = x \\
144
%\symm & \forall x, y. (x = y \limp y = x )\\
145
%\trans & \forall x , y , z . ( x = y \limp y = z \limp x = z ) \\
146
%\subst_f & \forall \vec x , \vec y . (\vec x = \vec y \limp f(\vec x) = f(\vec y) ) \\
147
%\subst_P & \forall \vec x , \vec y. (\vec x = \vec y \limp P(\vec x) \limp P(\vec y)  )
148
% \end{array}
149
%\left\{
150
\begin{equation}
151
\label{eqn:equality-theory}
152
\begin{array}{l}
153
\forall x . x = x \quad, \quad \forall x, y. (x = y \limp y = x )\quad, \quad \forall x , y , z . ( x = y \limp y = z \limp x = z ) \\ \forall \vec x , \vec y . (\vec x = \vec y \limp f(\vec x) = f(\vec y) )  \quad , \quad \forall \vec x , \vec y. (\vec x = \vec y \limp P(\vec x) \limp P(\vec y)  )
154
\end{array}
155
\end{equation}
156
%\right\}
157
% \]
158
  where $\vec x = \vec y$ is shorthand for $x_1 = y_1 \land \vldots \land x_n = y_n$.
159
    
160
\newcommand{\init}{\mathit{init}}    
161
We consider \emph{systems} of `nonlogical' rules extending Dfn.~\ref{def:LLsequentcalculus}, which we write as follows,
162
 \[
163
 \begin{array}{cc}
164
  \vlinf{\init}{}{ \seqar A}{}  &  \vlinf{(R)}{}{ !\Gamma , \Sigma' \seqar \Delta' , ? \Pi  }{ \{!\Gamma , \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i , ? \Pi \}_{i \in I} }
165
\end{array}
166
\]
167
 where, in each rule $(R)$, $I$ is a finite possibly empty set (indicating the number of premises) and we assume the following conditions and terminology:
168
 \begin{enumerate}
169
 \item In $(R)$ the formulas of $\Sigma', \Delta'$  are called \textit{principal}, those of $\Sigma_i, \Delta_i$ are called \textit{active}, and those of   
170
$ !\Gamma,  ? \Pi$ are called \textit{context formulas}. In $\init$ $A$ is called a principal formula.
171
\item Each rule $(R)$ comes with a list $a_1$, \dots, $a_k$ of eigenvariables such that each $a_j$ appears in exactly one $\Sigma_i, \Delta_i$ (so in some active formulas of exactly one premise)  and does not appear in  $\Sigma', \Delta'$ or $ !\Gamma,  ? \Pi$.
172
    \item A system $\system$ of rules must be closed under substitutions of free variables by terms (where these substitutions do not contain the eigenvariables $a_j$ in their domain or codomain).  
173
   \item  In $(R)$  the sequent $ \Sigma'$ (resp. $\Delta'$) does not contain any formula of the shape $?B$ (resp. $!B$), and  in $\init$ the formula $A$ is not of the form  $!B$.
174
 \end{enumerate}
175
 
176
%The distinction between modal and nonmodal formulae in $(R)$ induces condition 1
177
 Conditions 2 and 3 are standard requirements for nonlogical rules, independently of the logical setting, cf.\ \cite{Beckmann11}. Condition 2 reflects the intuitive idea that, in our nonlogical rules, we often need a notion of \textit{bound} variables in the active formulas (typically for induction rules), for which we rely on eigenvariables. Condition 3 is needed for our proof system to admit elimination of cuts on quantified formulas. Condition 4 
178
% and the conventions of 1 
179
 is peculiar to our linear logic setting in order to carry out certain proof-theoretic manipulations for the free-cut elimination argument in Sect.~\ref{sect:free-cut-elim}.
180
%  
181

    
182

    
183
 Observe that $\init$ rules can actually be seen as particular cases of $(R)$ rules, with no premise, so in the following we will only consider $(R)$ rules.
184
 
185
  
186
%  \patrick{Anupam: note that I had to strengthen the conditions for the rules (R). Condition (1) is needed 
187
%  to be able to commute a cut with (R), in the case where this cut is with a principal formula of a   ($\rigrul{!}$) rule. 
188
%  
189
%  Condition (2) is a sufficient condition to avoid the following situation: cut between a principal formula in say $\Delta'$ in the conclusion of an (R) rule (left premise), and a context formula in $!\Gamma$ in the conclusion of another (R) rule (right premise). Indeed this is not an anchored cut in our sense, but we cannot eliminate it in general (because we cannot commute the cut with (R) up the right premise).
190
%  }
191
  
192

    
193
  
194
    
195
    To each theory $\theory$ we formally associate the system of $\init$ rules $\seqar A$ for each $A \in \theory$.\footnote{Notice that this naively satisfies condition 3 since theories consist of only closed formulae.}  A proof in such a system will be called a \textit{ $\mathcal T$-proof}, or just {proof} when there is no risk of confusion.
196

    
197

    
198

    
199

    
200
%    
201
%  
202
%  In what follows we will be interested in an example of theory  $\mathcal T$ which is a form of arithmetic.
203
   
204
%   Let us give an example of a possible nonlogical rule that appears later in Sect.~\ref{sect:arithmetic}:
205
%   
206
%   \[
207
%	\vliinf{\ind}{}{ !\word(t), !\Gamma , A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t) , ?\Delta }{!\Gamma , !\word(a), A(a) \seqar A(s_0 a ), ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma , !\word(a), A(a) \seqar A(s_1 a ), ?\Delta }
208
%\]
209
%
210
%So here we have $I=\{0,1\}$ (two premises), $\Sigma_i=!\word(a), A(a)$ and $\Delta_i= A(s_i a )$ for $i=0,1$, $\Sigma'= !\word(t), A(\epsilon)$, $\Delta'= A(t)$. So condition 2 is satisfied provided $a\notin FV(!\Gamma, ?\Delta)$ and $a \notin FV(t)$. 
211

    
212

    
213
%\[
214
%	\vliinf{}{(x \notin \FV(\Gamma, \Delta))}{ !\Gamma , A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t) , ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma , A(x) \seqar A(s_0 x ), ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma, A(x) \seqar A( s_1 x ) , ?\Delta}
215
%	\]
216

    
217
  
218
%  A proof in such a system will be called a \textit{ $\mathcal T$-proof}, or just \textit{proof} when there is no risk of confusion.
219
%   The rules of Def. \ref{def:LLsequentcalculus} are called \textit{logical rules} while the rules (ax) and (R) of $\mathcal T$  are called \textit{non-logical}.
220
%  
221
%  As usual rules come with a notion of \textit{principal formulas}, which are a subset of the rules in the conclusion, e.g.:
222
%  $A \lor B$ in rule $\lefrul{\lor}$ (and similarly for all rules for connectives); $?A$ in rule $\rigrul{\cntr}$; all conclusion formulas in axiom rules;
223
%   $\Sigma', \Delta'$ in rule (R).
224
  
225
 
226
% \anupam{15/04: add definitions of theories and systems, unions, rules vs axioms etc. and abuses of notation:
227
% 	sometimes use same symbol for theory and system if fixed in advance;
228
% 	sometimes coincide axiom with initial rule;
229
% 	}
230

    
231

    
232
\begin{remark}
233
	[Semantics]
234
	The models we consider are usual Henkin models, with linear connectives interpreted by their classical counterparts. Consequently, we do not have any completeness theorem for our theories, but we do have soundness.
235
\end{remark}
236

    
237
 
238
\subsection{Some basic proof-theoretic results}
239
We briefly survey some well-known results for theories of linear logic.
240

    
241
A rule is \emph{invertible} if each of its upper sequents is derivable from its lower sequent.
242
\begin{proposition}
243
[Invertible rules, folklore]
244
\label{prop:invertible-rules}
245
The rules $\lefrul{\land}, \rigrul{\lor}, \lefrul{\laor}, \rigrul{\laand}, \lefrul{\exists}, \rigrul{\forall}$ are invertible.
246
\end{proposition}
247
We will typically write $\inv{c}$ to denote the inverse derivation for a logical symbol $c$.
248

    
249
%[cite Avron:`semantics and proof theory of linear logic']
250
%
251
%We will make much use of the deduction theorem, allowing us to argue informally within a theory for hypotheses that have been promoted.
252
%
253
%%$$
254
%%	\vliiinf{}{}{ \seqar A}{ \seqar C}
255
%%	$$
256
%
257
%%\[
258
%%	\vliiinf{R}{}{ !\Gamma , \Sigma' \seqar \Delta' , ? \Pi  }{ \{!\Gamma , \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i , ? \Pi \}_{i \in I} }
259
%%	\]
260

    
261
We also rely on the following result, which is also folklore but appeared before in \cite{Avron88}.
262

    
263
\begin{theorem}
264
	[Deduction, folklore]
265
	\label{thm:deduction}
266
	For any theory $\theory$ and closed formula $A $, $\mathcal T \cup\{A\}$ proves $B$ if and only if $\mathcal{T}$ proves $!A \limp B$.
267
\end{theorem}
268

    
269
%The occurrence of $!$ in the deduction theorem above is crucial; this restriction is one of the reasons it can be difficult to reason informally in theories over linear logic.
270

    
271

    
272
Due to these results notice that, in place of the equality axioms, we can work in a quantifier-free system of rules:
273
\begin{proposition}
274
	[Equality rules]
275
	\eqref{eqn:equality-theory} is equivalent to the following system of rules,
276
	\[
277
	\vlinf{}{}{\seqar t = t}{}
278
	\qquad
279
	\vlinf{}{}{s = t \seqar t = s}{}
280
	\qquad 
281
	\vlinf{}{}{r = s, s= t \seqar r = t}{}
282
	\qquad 
283
	\vlinf{}{}{\vec s = \vec t \seqar f(\vec s) = f(\vec t)}{}
284
	\qquad
285
	\vlinf{}{}{\vec s = \vec t, P(\vec s) \seqar P(\vec t)}{}
286
	\]
287
	where $r,s,t $ range over terms.
288
\end{proposition}
289

    
290

    
291

    
292

    
293

    
294
%\subsection{Converting axioms to rules in $\MELLW$}
295
%
296
%\begin{proposition}
297
%	An axiom $\Ax$ of the form,
298
%	\[
299
%	A_1 \limp \vldots \limp A_m \limp !B_1 \limp \vldots \limp !B_n \limp C
300
%	\]
301
%	is equivalent (over propositional $\LL$) to the rule $\Rl$:
302
%	\[
303
%	\vliiinf{\Rl}{}{ !\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ? \Delta  }{ !\Gamma \seqar B_1 , ?\Delta }{\vldots }{ !\Gamma \seqar B_n , ?\Delta}
304
%	\]
305
%\end{proposition}
306
%\begin{proof}
307
%	Let us first assume $\Ax$ and derive $\Rl$. From the axiom and Currying, we have a proof of:
308
%	\begin{equation}\label{eqn:curried-axiom}
309
%	A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C
310
%	\end{equation}
311
%	
312
%	This can simply be cut against each of the premisses of $\Rl$, applying appropriate contractions and necessitations, to derive it:
313
%	\[
314
%	\vlderivation{
315
%		\vliq{c}{}{!\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ?\Delta }{
316
%			\vliin{\cut}{}{!\Gamma, \dots , !\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ?\Delta, \dots , ?\Delta }{
317
%				\vlin{!}{}{!\Gamma \seqar !B_n, ?\Delta }{\vlhy{!\Gamma \seqar B_n , ?\Delta }}
318
%			}{
319
%			\vliin{\cut}{}{\qquad \qquad \qquad \qquad  \vlvdots \qquad \qquad \qquad \qquad }{
320
%				\vlin{!}{}{!\Gamma \seqar !B_1 , ?\Delta}{\vlhy{!\Gamma \seqar B_1, ?\Delta }}
321
%			}{\vlhy{ A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C } }
322
%		}
323
%	}
324
%}
325
%\]
326
%
327
%Now let us prove $\Ax$ (again in the form of \eqref{eqn:curried-axiom}) by using $\Rl$ as follows:
328
%\[
329
%\vliiinf{\Rl}{}{ A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C }{  \vlderivation{
330
%		\vlin{w}{}{ !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar B_1 }{
331
%			\vlin{!}{}{!B_1 \seqar B_1 }{
332
%				\vlin{\id}{}{B_1 \seqar B_1 }{\vlhy{}}
333
%			}
334
%		}
335
%	}  }{\vldots}{
336
%	\vlderivation{
337
%		\vlin{w}{}{ !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar B_n }{
338
%			\vlin{!}{}{!B_n \seqar B_n }{
339
%				\vlin{\id}{}{B_n \seqar B_n }{\vlhy{}}
340
%			}
341
%		}
342
%	}
343
%}
344
%\]
345
%\end{proof}
346
%
347
%
348
%\textbf{NB:} The proof does not strictly require side formulae $? \Delta$ on the right of the sequent arrow $\seqar$, it would work without them, e.g.\ for the intuitionistic case. In a one-sided setting there is no difference.
349
%
350
%
351
%
352
%\begin{corollary}
353
%	The induction axiom of $A^1_2$ is equivalent to the rule:
354
%	\[
355
%	\vliinf{}{(x \notin \FV(\Gamma, \Delta))}{ !\Gamma , !N(t), A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t) , ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma , !N(x), A(x) \seqar A(s_0 x ), ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma, !N(x),  A(x) \seqar A( s_1 x ) , ?\Delta}
356
%	\]
357
%\end{corollary}
358
%\begin{proof}
359
%	By proposition above, generalisation and Currying.
360
%\end{proof}
361
%
362
%\begin{proposition}
363
% The following induction rule is derivable from the one of the previous corollary:
364
%\[
365
%	\vliinf{}{(a, \vec{v}, \vec{x} \notin \FV(\Gamma, \Delta))}{ !\Gamma , !N(\vec{w}), N(\vec{y}), !N(t)  \seqar A(t,\vec{w},\vec{y}) , ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma ,  !N(\vec{v}), N(\vec{x}) \seqar A(\epsilon,\vec{v},\vec{x}), ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma ,  !N(\vec{v}), N(\vec{x}),    A(a,\vec{v},\vec{x}) \seqar  A(s_ia,\vec{v},\vec{x}) , ?\Delta}
366
%	\]
367
%where the second premise corresponds actually to two premises, one for $i=0$ and one for $i=1$.
368
%\end{proposition}
369
%\subsection{Prenexing}
370
%%In the presence of weakening we have a prenex normal form due to the following:
371
%%
372
%%\[
373
%%\vlderivation{
374
%%	\vlin{}{}{\exists x . A \lor B \seqar \exists x . (A(x) \lor B) }{
375
%%		
376
%%		}
377
%%	}
378
%%\]
379
%
380
%Cannot derive prenexing operations, e.g.\ a problem with $\exists x . A \lor B \seqar \exists x . (A(x) \lor B)$. Can safely add prenexing rules? Or not a problem due to Witness predicate?