root / CSL16 / final-version / free-cut-elim.tex @ 118
Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (20,42 ko)
1 |
\section{Free-cut elimination in linear logic} |
---|---|
2 |
\label{sect:free-cut-elim} |
3 |
% While in plain logical systems such as linear logic cut rules can be eliminated, this is in general not the case anymore when one considers extension with a theory $\mathcal T$ . For this reason we need now to define the kind of cuts that will remain in proofs after reduction. We will call these \textit{anchored cuts}. |
4 |
We need first to define which cuts will remain in proofs after reduction. |
5 |
% They are called \textit{anchored cuts}. |
6 |
% Our first idea would be to consider as anchored a cut whose cut-formulas $A$ in the two premises are both principal for their rule, and at least one of these rules is non-logical. Now, the problem with this tentative definition is that a rule (R) of $\mathcal T$ can contain several principal formulas (in $\Sigma'$, $\Delta'$) and so we would like to allow an anchored cut on each of these principal formulas. |
7 |
% % Consider for instance the following derivation, where we have underlined principal formulas: |
8 |
% See for instance (the principal formulas are underlined): |
9 |
% \patrick{Anupam, could you please display this derivation in a suitable way?} |
10 |
% \[ |
11 |
% \vlderivation{ |
12 |
%\vliin{cut_2}{}{ \seqar \Delta}{ |
13 |
%\vliin{cut_1}{}{\seqar A_2 }{\vlin{\rigrul{\lor}}{}{\seqar \underline{A_1}}{}}{\vliin{(R)}{}{\underline{A_1}\seqar \underline{A_2}}{}{} } |
14 |
%}{ |
15 |
%\vliin{\lefrul{\land}}{}{\underline{A_2}\seqar \Delta}{}{} |
16 |
%} |
17 |
%} |
18 |
%\] |
19 |
% Here $cut_1$ is anchored in this sense, but not $cut_2$. Therefore we propose a more general definition: |
20 |
Since our nonlogical rules may have many principal formulae on which we permit cuts to be anchored, we need a slightly more general notion than `principal formula'. |
21 |
\begin{definition}\label{def:anchoredcut} |
22 |
We define in a mutual inductive way the notion of \textit{hereditarily principal formula} and \textit{anchored cut} in a $\system$-proof for a system $\system$: |
23 |
\begin{itemize} |
24 |
\item A formula $A$ in a sequent $\Gamma \seqar \Delta$ is \textit{hereditarily principal} for a rule (S), if either (i) the sequent is in the conclusion (S) and $A$ is principal in it, or |
25 |
(ii) the sequent is in the conclusion of an anchored cut, the direct ancestor of $A$ in the corresponding premise is hereditarily principal for the rule (S), and the rule (S) is nonlogical. |
26 |
\item A cut-step is an \textit{anchored cut} if either of its cut-formulas $A$ in the two premises are both hereditarily principal for nonlogical steps, or one is hereditarily principal for a nonlogical step and the other one is principal for a logical step. |
27 |
\end{itemize} |
28 |
\end{definition} |
29 |
As a consequence of this definition, an anchored cut on a formula $A$ has the following properties: |
30 |
\begin{itemize} |
31 |
\item At least one of the two premises of the cut has above it a sub-branch of the proof which starts (top-down) with a nonlogical rule (R) with $A$ as one of its principal formulas, and then a sequence of anchored cuts in which $A$ is part of the context. |
32 |
\item The other premise is either of the same form, or a logical step with principal formula $A$. |
33 |
\end{itemize} |
34 |
|
35 |
% Now, for instance a cut on a (principal) formula $A \lor B$ between a rule $\rigrul{\lor}$ and a rule (R) (where $A \lor B$ occurs in $\Sigma'$) is anchored, while a cut between |
36 |
% a rule $\rigrul{\lor}$ and a rule $\lefrul{\lor}$ is not. |
37 |
|
38 |
A cut which is not anchored will also be called a \textit{free-cut}. |
39 |
|
40 |
% With this new definition both $cut_1$ and $cut_2$ in the previous example are anchored. |
41 |
|
42 |
% \patrick{@Anupam: if we need to shorten this part, I think we should anyway keep the key lemmas \ref{lem:hereditaryprincipalnonlogical} and \ref{lem:keycommutations}. In the proof of the thm itself, I would give priority to keep the first case, maybe by skipping the first situation and keeping the second item, $S_1$=$!r$, $?l$ or $R$. Second case could be kept too, and third case could be briefly summarized and pushed in the appendix or online version.} |
43 |
|
44 |
% Let us first prove a key lemma on hereditarily principal formulas: |
45 |
Due to condition 4 in Sect.~\ref{sect:preliminaries}, we have the following: |
46 |
\begin{lemma}\label{lem:hereditaryprincipalnonlogical} |
47 |
A formula occurrence $A$ on the LHS (resp.\ RHS) of a sequent and hereditarily principal for a nonlogical rule (R) |
48 |
cannot be of the form $A=?A'$ (resp. $A=!A'$). |
49 |
\end{lemma} |
50 |
|
51 |
|
52 |
Now we can state the main result of this section: |
53 |
\begin{theorem} |
54 |
[Free-cut elimination] |
55 |
\label{thm:free-cut-elim} |
56 |
Given a system $\system$, any $\system$-proof $\pi$ can be transformed into a $\system$-proof $\pi'$ with same conclusion sequent and without any free-cuts. |
57 |
\end{theorem} |
58 |
%The proof will be given below. It will proceed |
59 |
The proof proceeds in a way similar to the classical proof of cut elimination for linear logic, |
60 |
%, but here for eliminating only free-cuts, and one has to check that all steps of the reasoning are compatible with the fact that the proof here also contains $\mathcal{T}$ rules. |
61 |
%% Define the \textit{degree} of a formula as the number of logical connectives or quantifiers in it. Let us first state an easy building-block of the proof, which comes from standard linear logic: |
62 |
%% \begin{lemma}[Logical non-exponential cut-elimination steps]\label{lem:logical steps} |
63 |
%% Any cut $c$ whose cut-formulas $A$ are both principal formulas of logical rules distinct from $?$, $!$, $wk$, $cntr$ rules can be replaced in one step by cuts on formulas of strictly lower degree (0, 1 or 2 cuts). |
64 |
%% \end{lemma} |
65 |
%% \begin{proof} |
66 |
%% This is exactly as in plain linear logic. Just note that the case of a quantifier formula involves a substitution by a term $t$ throughout the proof, and this is where we need condition 3 on non-logical rules requiring that they are closed by substitution. |
67 |
%% \end{proof} |
68 |
% Actually the most important part of the proof of Thm \ref{thm:free-cut-elim} is the handling of the commutation steps, since this is where the new non-logical rules could raise some problems. |
69 |
but eliminating only free-cuts and verifying compatibility with our notion of nonlogical rule, in particular for the commutation cases. |
70 |
|
71 |
First, observe that the only rules in which there is a condition on the context are the following ones: $(\rigrul{\forall})$, $(\lefrul{\exists})$, $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$. These are thus the rules for which the commutation with cut steps are not straightforward. Commutations with logical rules other than $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$ are done in the standard way, as in pure linear logic:\footnote{Note that, for the $(\rigrul{\forall})$, $(\lefrul{\exists})$ rules, there might also be a global renaming of eigenvariables if necessary.} |
72 |
\begin{lemma}[Standard commutations]\label{lem:standardcommutations} |
73 |
Any logical rule distinct from $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$ can be commuted top-down with any cut $c$. If the logical rule is binary this will produce two cuts. |
74 |
\end{lemma} |
75 |
|
76 |
|
77 |
% In the following we will need to be more careful about rules $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$. For that we establish our second key lemma: |
78 |
For rules $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$ we establish our second key lemma: |
79 |
\begin{lemma}[Key commutations]\label{lem:keycommutations} |
80 |
A cut of the following form, where $?A$ is non principal for $(R)$, can be commuted with the $(R)$ rule: |
81 |
\[ |
82 |
\vliinf{cut}{}{ !\Gamma', \Gamma, \Sigma' \seqar \Delta', ?A, ?\Pi, ?\Pi'} |
83 |
{ \vlinf{(R)}{}{!\Gamma, \Sigma' \seqar \Delta', ?A, ?\Pi}{ \{ !\Gamma, \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i, ?A, ?\Pi \}_{i\in I} } } |
84 |
{ |
85 |
% \vlinf{}{}{?A, !\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi'}{} |
86 |
?A, !\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi' |
87 |
} |
88 |
\] |
89 |
Similarly if $(R)$ is replaced with $(\rigrul{!})$, with $?A$ in its RHS context, and also for the symmetric situations: |
90 |
cut on the LHS of the conclusion of an $(R)$ or a $(\lefrul{?})$ step on a (non-principal) formula $!A$, with a sequent $!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi', !A$. |
91 |
\end{lemma} |
92 |
\begin{proof} |
93 |
The left subderivation can be replaced by: |
94 |
\[ |
95 |
\vlinf{(R)}{}{ !\Gamma', !\Gamma, \Sigma' \seqar \Delta', ?\Pi, ?\Pi'} |
96 |
{ \vliinf{cut}{}{\{!\Gamma', !\Gamma, \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i, ?\Pi,?\Pi' \}_{i\in I}} { |
97 |
% \vlinf{}{}{ !\Gamma, \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i, ?A, ?\Pi}{} |
98 |
!\Gamma, \Sigma_i \seqar \Delta_i, ?A, ?\Pi |
99 |
} { |
100 |
% \vlinf{}{}{?A, !\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi'}{} |
101 |
?A, !\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi' |
102 |
} } |
103 |
\] |
104 |
Here if an eigenvariable in $\Sigma_i, \Delta_i$ happens to be free in $!\Gamma', ?\Pi'$ we rename it to avoid the collision, which is possible because by condition 2 on non-logical rules these eigenvariables do not appear in $\Sigma', \Delta'$ or $!\Gamma, ?\Pi$. So the occurrence of $(R)$ in this new subderivation is valid. |
105 |
|
106 |
Similarly for the symmetric derivation with a cut on the LHS of the conclusion of an $(R)$ on a formula $!A$. |
107 |
The analogous situations with rules $(\rigrul{!})$ and $(\lefrul{?})$ are handled in the same way, as usual in linear logic. |
108 |
\end{proof} |
109 |
%Now we have all the necessary lemmas to proceed with the proof of the theorem. |
110 |
|
111 |
Now we can prove the main free-cut elimination result: |
112 |
\begin{proof}[Proof sketch of Thm.~\ref{thm:free-cut-elim}] |
113 |
Given a cut step $c$ in a proof $\pi$, we call \emph{degree} $\deg( c)$ the number of connectives and quantifiers of its cut-formula. Now the \emph{degree} of the proof $\deg( \pi)$ is the multiset of the degrees of its non-anchored formulas. The degrees will be compared with the multiset ordering. |
114 |
The demonstration proceeds by induction on the degree $\deg( \pi)$. For a given degree we proceed with a sub-induction on the \textit{height} $\height{\pi}$ of the proof. |
115 |
|
116 |
Consider a proof $\pi$ of non-null degree. We want to show how to reduce it to a proof of strictly lower degree. Consider a top-most non-anchored cut $c$ in $\pi$, that is to say such that there is no non-anchored cut above $c$. Let us call $A$ the cut-formula, and $(S_1)$ (resp. $(S_2)$) the rule above the left (resp. right) premise of $c$. |
117 |
\[ |
118 |
\vliinf{c \; \; \cut}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi}{ \vlinf{S_1}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A}{} }{\vlinf{S_2}{}{\Sigma, A \seqar \Pi}{}} |
119 |
\] |
120 |
Intuitively we proceed as follows: if $A$ is not hereditarily principal in one of its premises we try to commute $c$ with the rule along its left premise $(S_1)$, and if not possible then commute it with the rule along its right premise $(S_2)$, by Lemmas \ref{lem:hereditaryprincipalnonlogical} and \ref{lem:standardcommutations}. If $A$ is hereditarily principal in both premises we proceed with a cut-elimination step, as in standard linear logic. For this second step, the delicate part is the elimination of exponential cuts, for which we use a big-step reduction. This works because the contexts in the nonlogical rules $(R)$ are marked with $!$ (resp. $?$) on the LHS (resp. RHS). |
121 |
% See the appendix for the full proof. |
122 |
\end{proof} |
123 |
|
124 |
% \begin{itemize} |
125 |
% \item \textbf{First case}: the cut-formula $A$ on the l.h.s. of $c$ is non hereditarily principal. |
126 |
% |
127 |
%\begin{itemize} |
128 |
%\item Consider first the situation where $(S_1)$ is not one of the rules $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$. |
129 |
% |
130 |
%In this case the commutation of $c$ with $(S_1)$ can be done in the usual way, by using Lemma \ref{lem:standardcommutations}. Let us handle as an example the case where $(S_1)=(\rigrul{\laand})$. |
131 |
%{\small |
132 |
%\[ |
133 |
%\vlderivation{ |
134 |
%\vliin{c}{}{ \Gamma, \Sigma \seqar B_1\vlan B_2, \Delta, \Pi }{ \vliin{S_1=\rigrul{\vlan}}{}{\Gamma \seqar B_1\vlan B_2, \Delta, A}{ \vlhy{\Gamma \seqar B_1, \Delta, A} }{\vlhy{\Gamma \seqar B_2,\Delta, A}}}{ \vlhy{ \Sigma, A \seqar \Pi} } |
135 |
%} |
136 |
%\quad\to\quad |
137 |
%\vlderivation{ |
138 |
%\vliin{\rigrul{\vlan}}{}{ \Gamma, \Sigma \seqar B_1\vlan B_2, \Delta, \Pi }{ |
139 |
%\vliin{c_1}{}{\Gamma,\Sigma \seqar B_1, \Delta, \Pi }{ \vlhy{\Gamma \seqar B_1, \Delta, A} }{\vlhy{ \Sigma, A \seqar \Pi} } |
140 |
%}{ |
141 |
%\vliin{c_2}{}{\Gamma,\Sigma \seqar B_2, \Delta, \Pi }{ \vlhy{\Gamma \seqar B_2, \Delta, A} }{\vlhy{ \Sigma, A \seqar \Pi} } |
142 |
%} |
143 |
%} |
144 |
%\] |
145 |
%} |
146 |
% |
147 |
%Observe that here $c$ is replaced by two cuts $c_1$ and $c_2$. Call $\pi_i$ the sub-derivation of last rule $c_i$, for $i=1,2$. As for $i=1, 2$ we have |
148 |
%$\deg{\pi_i}\leq \deg{\pi}$ and $\height{\pi_i}< \height{\pi}$ we can apply the induction hypothesis, and reduce $\pi_i$ to a proof $\pi'_i$ of same conclusion and with |
149 |
%$\deg{\pi'_i} < \deg{\pi_i}$. Therefore by replacing $\pi_i$ by $\pi'_i$ for $i=1, 2$ we obtain a proof $\pi'$ such that $\deg{\pi'}<\deg{\pi}$. |
150 |
% |
151 |
%The case (S)=($\lefrul{\laor}$) is identical, and the other cases are similar. % (see the Appendix for more examples). |
152 |
% |
153 |
%\item Consider now the case where $(S_1)$ is equal to $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$ or $(R)$. Let us also assume that the cut-formula is hereditarily principal in its r.h.s. premise, because if this does not hold we can move to the second case below. |
154 |
% |
155 |
%First consider $(S_1)=(\rigrul{!})$. As $A$ is not principal in the conclusion of $(\rigrul{!})$ it is of the form $A=?A'$. By assumption we know that $A=?A'$ in the conclusion of $(S_2)$ is hereditarily principal on the l.h.s., so by Lemma \ref{lem:hereditaryprincipalnonlogical} it cannot be hereditarily principal for a non-logical rule, so by definition of hereditarily principal we deduce that $(S_2)$ is not an $(R)$ rule. It cannot be an $(\rigrul{!})$ rule either because then $?A'$ could not be a principal formula in its conclusion. Therefore the only possibility is that |
156 |
% $(S_2)$ is an $(\lefrul{?})$ rule. So the r.h.s. premise is of the shape $?A',!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi'$ and by Lemma \ref{lem:keycommutations} the commutation on the l.h.s. is possible. We can conclude as previously. The case where $(S_1)=(\lefrul{?})$ is the same. |
157 |
% |
158 |
% Now consider the case where $(S_1)=(R)$. As $A$ is not hereditarily principal in the conclusion of $(R)$, it is a context formula and it is on the r.h.s., so by definition of $(R)$ rules it is the form $A=?A'$. So as before by Lemma \ref{lem:hereditaryprincipalnonlogical} we deduce that $(S_2)=(\lefrul{?})$, and so the r.h.s. premise is of the shape $?A',!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Pi'$. By Lemma \ref{lem:keycommutations} the commutation on the l.h.s. is possible, and so again we conclude as previously. |
159 |
% \end{itemize} |
160 |
% \item \textbf{Second case}: the cut-formulas on the l.h.s. and r.h.s. of $c$ are both non hereditarily principal. |
161 |
% |
162 |
% After the first case we are here left with the situation where $(S_1)$ is equal to $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$ or $(R)$. |
163 |
% \begin{itemize} |
164 |
% \item Consider the case where $(S_1)$=$(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, so $A$ is of the form $A=?A'$. All cases of commutation of $c$ with $(S_2)$ are as in standard linear logic, except if $(S_2)=(R)$. In this case though we cannot have $A=?A'$ because of the shape of rule $(R)$. So we are done. |
165 |
% \item Consider $(S_1)=(R)$. Again as $A$ is not principal in the conclusion of $(S_1)$ and on the r.h.s. of the sequent it is a context formula, and thus of the form $A=?A'$. As $?A'$ is not principal in the conclusion of $(S_2)$, it is thus a context formula on the l.h.s. of sequent, and therefore $(S_2)$ is not a rule $(R)$. So $(S_2)$ is a logical rule. If it is not an $(\rigrul{!})$ or an $(\lefrul{?})$ it admits commutation with the cut, and we are done. If it is equal to $(\rigrul{!})$ or $(\lefrul{?})$ it cannot have $?A'$ as a context formula in the l.h.s. of its conclusion, so these subcases do not occur. |
166 |
% \end{itemize} |
167 |
% |
168 |
% |
169 |
% \item \textbf{Third case}: the cut-formulas on the l.h.s. and r.h.s. of $c$ are both hereditarily principal. |
170 |
% |
171 |
% By assumption $c$ is non anchored, so none of the two cut-formulas is hereditarily principal for a non-logical rule $(R)$. We can deduce from that |
172 |
% that the l.h.s. cut-formula is principal for $(S_1)$ and the r.h.s. cut-formula is principal for $(S_2)$. Call $\pi_1$ (resp. $\pi_2$) the subderivation |
173 |
% of last rule $(S_1)$ (resp. $(S_2)$). |
174 |
% |
175 |
% Then we consider the following sub-cases, in order: |
176 |
% \begin{itemize} |
177 |
% \item \textbf{weakening sub-case}: this is the case when one of the premises of $c$ is a $wk$ rule. W.l.o.g. assume that it is the left premise of $c$ which is conclusion of $\rigrul{\wk}$, with principal formula $A$. We eliminate the cut by keeping only the l.h.s. proof $\pi_1$, removing the last cut $c$ and last $\rigrul{\wk}$ rule on $A$, and by adding enough |
178 |
% $\rigrul{\wk}$, $\lefrul{\wk}$ rules to introduce all the new formulas in the final sequent. The degree has decreased. |
179 |
% |
180 |
% \item \textbf{exponential sub-case}: this is when one of the premises of $c$ is conclusion of a $cntr$, $\rigrul{?}$ or $\lefrul{!}$ rule on a formula $?A$ or $!A$, and the other one is not a conclusion of $\wk$. |
181 |
% |
182 |
% Assume w.l.o.g. that it is the right premise which is conclusion of $\lefrul{\cntr}$ or $\lefrul{!}$ on $!A$, and thus the only possibility for the left premise is to be conclusion of $\rigrul{!}$. This is rule $(S_1)$ on the picture, last rule of the subderivation $\pi_1$, and we denote its conclusion as $!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Delta', !A$. We will use here a global rewriting step. For that consider in $\pi_2$ all the top-most direct ancestors of the cut-formula $!A$, that is to say direct ancestors which do not have any more direct ancestors above. Let us denote them as $!A^{j}$ for $1\leq j \leq k$. Observe that each $!A^{j}$ is principal formula of a rule $\lefrul{!}$ or $\lefrul{wk}$. Denote by $\rho$ the subderivation |
183 |
% of $\pi_2$ which has as leaves the sequents premises of these $\lefrul{!}$ or $\lefrul{wk}$ rules with conclusion containing $!A^{j}$. |
184 |
% Let $\rho'$ be a derivation obtained from $\rho$ by renaming if necessary eigenvariables occurring in premises of rules $\lefrul{\exists}$, $\rigrul{\forall}$, $(R)$ so that none of them belongs to $FV(!\Gamma', ?\Delta')$, where we recall that $!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Delta',!A$ is the l.h.s. premise of the cut $c$. |
185 |
% Now, let $\pi'_1$ be the immediate subderivation of $\pi_1$, of conclusion $!\Gamma' \seqar ?\Delta',A$. We then define the derivation |
186 |
% $\rho''$ obtained from $\rho'$ in the following way: |
187 |
% \begin{itemize} |
188 |
% \item add a cut $c_j$ with (a copy) of $\pi'_1$ on $A^j$ at each leaf which is premise of a rule $\lefrul{!}$; |
189 |
% \item add to each sequent coming from $\rho'$ an additional context $!\Gamma'$ on the l.h.s. and an additional context $?\Delta'$ on the r.h.s., and additional $wk$ rules to introduce these formulas below the $\lefrul{wk}$ rules on formulas $!A^{j}$; |
190 |
% \item introduce suitable $\lefrul{cntr}$ and $\rigrul{cntr}$ rules after multiplicative binary rules $\rigrul{\land}$, $\lefrul{\lor}$ in such a way to replace $!\Gamma', !\Gamma'$ (resp. $?\Delta', ?\Delta'$) by $!\Gamma'$ (resp. $?\Delta'$). |
191 |
% \end{itemize} |
192 |
% |
193 |
% It can be checked that $\rho''$ is a valid derivation, because all the conditions for context-sensitive rules $(\rigrul{\forall})$, $(\lefrul{\exists})$, $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$ are satisfied. In particular the rules $(\rigrul{!})$, $(\lefrul{?})$, $(R)$ are satisfied because the contexts have been enlarged with $!$ formulas on the l.h.s. of the sequents ($!\Gamma'$) and ? formulas on the r.h.s. of the sequents ($?\Gamma'$). |
194 |
% |
195 |
% Now, let $\pi'$ be the derivation obtained from $\pi$ by removing the cut $c$ and replacing the subderivation $\rho$ by $\rho''$. The derivation $\pi'$ is a valid one, it has the same conclusion $!\Gamma', \Sigma \seqar ?\Delta', \Pi$ and with respect to $\pi$ we have replaced one non-anchored cut $c$ with at most $k$ ones $c_j$, but which are of strictly lower degree. So $\deg(\pi')<\deg(\pi)$ and we are done. |
196 |
% |
197 |
% |
198 |
% \item \textbf{logical sub-case}: we are now left with the case where both premises of $c$ are conclusions of rules others than $?$, $!$, $wk$, $cntr$. We can thus apply Lemma \ref{lem:logical steps}. |
199 |
% If one of the premises is an axiom $\lefrul{\bot}$, $\id$ or $\rigrul{\bot}$, then $\pi$ can be rewritten to a suitable proof $\pi'$ by removing $c$ and the axiom rule. Otherwise both premises introduce the same connective, either $\land$, $\lor$, $\laor$, $\laand$, $\forall$ or $\exists$. In each case a specific rewriting rule replaces the cut $c$ with one cut of strictly lower degree. |
200 |
% %See the Appendix. |
201 |
% \end{itemize} |
202 |
% \end{itemize} |
203 |
% \end{proof} |