root / CSL16 / feas-arith-wfm.tex @ 10
Historique | Voir | Annoter | Télécharger (42,74 ko)
1 |
\documentclass[a4paper,UKenglish]{lipics-v2016} |
---|---|
2 |
%This is a template for producing LIPIcs articles. |
3 |
%See lipics-manual.pdf for further information. |
4 |
%for A4 paper format use option "a4paper", for US-letter use option "letterpaper" |
5 |
%for british hyphenation rules use option "UKenglish", for american hyphenation rules use option "USenglish" |
6 |
% for section-numbered lemmas etc., use "numberwithinsect" |
7 |
|
8 |
\usepackage{microtype}%if unwanted, comment out or use option "draft" |
9 |
|
10 |
%\graphicspath{{./graphics/}}%helpful if your graphic files are in another directory |
11 |
|
12 |
\bibliographystyle{plainurl}% the recommended bibstyle |
13 |
|
14 |
% Author macros::begin %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% |
15 |
\title{Free-cut elimination in linear logic: an application to implicit complexity} |
16 |
%\titlerunning{A Sample LIPIcs Article} %optional, in case that the title is too long; the running title should fit into the top page column |
17 |
|
18 |
%% Please provide for each author the \author and \affil macro, even when authors have the same affiliation, i.e. for each author there needs to be the \author and \affil macros |
19 |
\author[1]{Patrick Baillot} |
20 |
\author[2]{Anupam Das} |
21 |
\affil[1]{Dummy University Computing Laboratory, Address/City, Country\\ |
22 |
\texttt{open@dummyuniversity.org}} |
23 |
\affil[2]{Department of Informatics, Dummy College, Address/City, Country\\ |
24 |
\texttt{access@dummycollege.org}} |
25 |
\authorrunning{J.\,Q. Open and J.\,R. Access} %mandatory. First: Use abbreviated first/middle names. Second (only in severe cases): Use first author plus 'et. al.' |
26 |
|
27 |
\Copyright{John Q. Open and Joan R. Access}%mandatory, please use full first names. LIPIcs license is "CC-BY"; http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/ |
28 |
|
29 |
\subjclass{Dummy classification -- please refer to \url{http://www.acm.org/about/class/ccs98-html}}% mandatory: Please choose ACM 1998 classifications from http://www.acm.org/about/class/ccs98-html . E.g., cite as "F.1.1 Models of Computation". |
30 |
\keywords{Dummy keyword -- please provide 1--5 keywords}% mandatory: Please provide 1-5 keywords |
31 |
% Author macros::end %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% |
32 |
|
33 |
%Editor-only macros:: begin (do not touch as author)%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% |
34 |
\EventEditors{John Q. Open and Joan R. Acces} |
35 |
\EventNoEds{2} |
36 |
\EventLongTitle{42nd Conference on Very Important Topics (CVIT 2016)} |
37 |
\EventShortTitle{CVIT 2016} |
38 |
\EventAcronym{CVIT} |
39 |
\EventYear{2016} |
40 |
\EventDate{December 24--27, 2016} |
41 |
\EventLocation{Little Whinging, United Kingdom} |
42 |
\EventLogo{} |
43 |
\SeriesVolume{42} |
44 |
\ArticleNo{23} |
45 |
% Editor-only macros::end %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% |
46 |
|
47 |
|
48 |
|
49 |
\usepackage[lutzsyntax]{virginialake} |
50 |
\usepackage{amsmath} |
51 |
\usepackage{amssymb} |
52 |
\usepackage{amsthm} |
53 |
\usepackage{times} |
54 |
%\usepackage{sans} |
55 |
\usepackage{cmll} |
56 |
\usepackage{bm} |
57 |
|
58 |
%\newtheorem{theorem}{Theorem} |
59 |
%\newtheorem{maintheorem}[theorem]{Main Theorem} |
60 |
%\newtheorem{observation}[theorem]{Observation} |
61 |
%\newtheorem{corollary}[theorem]{Corollary} |
62 |
%\newtheorem{lemma}[theorem]{Lemma} |
63 |
\newtheorem{proposition}[theorem]{Proposition} |
64 |
%\newtheorem{conjecture}[theorem]{Conjecture} |
65 |
% |
66 |
%\theoremstyle{definition} |
67 |
%\newtheorem{definition}[theorem]{Definition} |
68 |
%\newtheorem{example}[theorem]{Example} |
69 |
%\newtheorem{notation}[theorem]{Notation} |
70 |
%\newtheorem{convention}[theorem]{Convention} |
71 |
%\newtheorem{remark}[theorem]{Remark} |
72 |
%\newtheorem{discussion}[theorem]{Discussion} |
73 |
|
74 |
\newcommand{\todo}[1]{{\color{red}{\textbf{Todo:} #1}}} |
75 |
\newcommand{\anupam}[1]{{\color{orange}{\textbf{Anupam:} #1}}} |
76 |
\newcommand{\patrick}[1]{{\color{blue}{\textbf{Patrick:} #1}}} |
77 |
|
78 |
\newcommand{\defined}{:=} |
79 |
\begin{document} |
80 |
|
81 |
\newcommand{\LL}{\it{LL}} |
82 |
\vllineartrue |
83 |
|
84 |
|
85 |
\newcommand{\FV}{\mathit{FV}} |
86 |
|
87 |
|
88 |
%terms |
89 |
\renewcommand{\succ}{s} |
90 |
\renewcommand{\epsilon}{\varepsilon} |
91 |
|
92 |
% linear connectives |
93 |
|
94 |
\newcommand{\limp}{\multimap} |
95 |
\renewcommand{\land}{\otimes} |
96 |
\newcommand{\laand}{\&} |
97 |
\newcommand{\laor}{\oplus} |
98 |
\renewcommand{\lor}{\vlpa} |
99 |
\renewcommand{\lnot}[1]{{#1^{\perp}}} |
100 |
\newcommand{\lnotnot}[1]{#1^{\perp \perp}} |
101 |
|
102 |
% classical connectives |
103 |
|
104 |
\newcommand{\cimp}{\supset} |
105 |
\newcommand{\cand}{\wedge} |
106 |
\newcommand{\cor}{\vee} |
107 |
\newcommand{\cnot}{\neg} |
108 |
|
109 |
|
110 |
\newcommand{\Ax}{\mathit{(Ax)}} |
111 |
\newcommand{\Rl}{\mathit{(Rl)}} |
112 |
|
113 |
\newcommand{\MELL}{\mathit{MELL}} |
114 |
\newcommand{\MEAL}{\mathit{MELLW}} |
115 |
\newcommand{\MELLW}{\mathit{MELL(W)}} |
116 |
|
117 |
\newcommand{\Aonetwo}{\mathcal{A}^1_2} |
118 |
\newcommand{\logic}{\mathit{L}_{\mathcal A} } |
119 |
|
120 |
% predicates |
121 |
\newcommand{\nat}{N} |
122 |
|
123 |
\newcommand{\Nat}{\mathbb{N}} |
124 |
|
125 |
%axioms |
126 |
\newcommand{\wk}{\mathit{wk}} |
127 |
\newcommand{\impl}{\cimp\text{-}\mathit{l}} |
128 |
\newcommand{\impcomm}{\mathit{com}} |
129 |
\newcommand{\conint}{\cand\text{-}\mathit{i}} |
130 |
\newcommand{\conel}{\cand\text{-}\mathit{e}} |
131 |
\newcommand{\negclass}{\cnot} |
132 |
|
133 |
%rules |
134 |
\renewcommand{\mp}{\mathit{mp}} |
135 |
\newcommand{\gen}{\mathit{gen}} |
136 |
\newcommand{\inst}{\mathit{ins}} |
137 |
\newcommand{\id}{\it{id}} |
138 |
\newcommand{\cut}{\it{cut}} |
139 |
\newcommand{\multicut}{\it{mcut}} |
140 |
\newcommand{\indr}{\mathit{IND}} |
141 |
\newcommand{\nec}{\mathit{nec}} |
142 |
\newcommand{\tax}{\mathit{T}} |
143 |
\newcommand{\four}{\mathit{4}} |
144 |
\newcommand{\kax}{\mathit{K}} |
145 |
\newcommand{\cntr}{\mathit{cntr}} |
146 |
|
147 |
\newcommand{\lefrul}[1]{#1\text{-}\mathit{l}} |
148 |
\newcommand{\rigrul}[1]{#1\text{-}\mathit{r}} |
149 |
|
150 |
%consequence relations |
151 |
\newcommand{\admits}{\vDash} |
152 |
\newcommand{\seqar}{\vdash} |
153 |
\newcommand{\proves}{\vdash_e} |
154 |
|
155 |
%induction |
156 |
\newcommand{\ind}{\mathit{IND}} |
157 |
\newcommand{\pind}{\mathit{PIND}} |
158 |
\newcommand{\cax}[2]{#1\text{-}#2} |
159 |
|
160 |
\maketitle |
161 |
|
162 |
\begin{abstract} |
163 |
We prove a general form of free-cut elimination for first-order theories in linear logic. We consider a version of Peano Arithmetic in linear logic and prove a witnessing theorem via the Buss and Mints \emph{witness function method}, characterising polytime as the provably total functions. |
164 |
\end{abstract} |
165 |
|
166 |
\section{Introduction} |
167 |
|
168 |
\todo{words or integers?} |
169 |
|
170 |
|
171 |
|
172 |
\section{Preliminaries} |
173 |
|
174 |
\todo{consider removing and just have a section on linear logic, including free-cut elimination.} |
175 |
|
176 |
|
177 |
|
178 |
|
179 |
\paragraph*{Notation} |
180 |
Fix conventions here for use throughout: |
181 |
\begin{itemize} |
182 |
\item Eigenvariables: $a, b , c$. |
183 |
\item (Normal) variables: $u,v,w$. (only when distinction is important, e.g.\ $u^{!\nat}$). |
184 |
\item (Safe) variables: $x,y,z$. (as above, e.g.\ $x^\nat$.) |
185 |
\item Terms: $r,s,t$. |
186 |
\item Formulae: $A,B,C$. |
187 |
\item Atomic formulae: $p,q$. |
188 |
\item Sequents: $\Gamma, \Delta, \Sigma, \Pi$. |
189 |
\item Proofs: $\pi, \rho, \sigma$. |
190 |
\item Theories: $\mathcal T$. Sequent systems: $\mathcal S$. |
191 |
\end{itemize} |
192 |
|
193 |
\subsection{Linear logic} |
194 |
|
195 |
\anupam{use a system that is already in De Morgan form, for simplicity.} |
196 |
\anupam{Have skipped units, can reconsider this when in arithmetic. Also in affine setting can be recovered by any contradiction/tautology.} |
197 |
|
198 |
\begin{definition} |
199 |
[Sequent calculus for linear logic] |
200 |
We define the following calculus in De Morgan normal form: |
201 |
\[ |
202 |
\begin{array}{l} |
203 |
\begin{array}{cccc} |
204 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\bot}}{}{p, \lnot{p} \seqar }{} |
205 |
& \vlinf{\id}{}{p \seqar p}{} |
206 |
& \vlinf{\rigrul{\bot}}{}{\seqar p, \lnot{p}}{} |
207 |
& \vliinf{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A }{\Sigma, A \seqar \Pi} |
208 |
\\ |
209 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
210 |
%\text{Multiplicatives:} & & & \\ |
211 |
%\noalign{\bigskip} |
212 |
\vliinf{\lefrul{\lor}}{}{\Gamma,\Sigma, A \lor B \seqar \Delta, \Pi}{\Gamma, A \seqar \Delta}{\Sigma , B \seqar \Pi} |
213 |
& |
214 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\land}}{}{\Gamma, A\land B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A , B \seqar \Delta} |
215 |
& |
216 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\lor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A \lor B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A, B} |
217 |
& |
218 |
\vliinf{\rigrul{\land}}{}{\Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi , A \land B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta , A}{\Sigma \seqar \Pi , B} |
219 |
\\ |
220 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
221 |
%\text{Additives:} & & & \\ |
222 |
%\noalign{\bigskip} |
223 |
\vliinf{\lefrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma, A \laor B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma , A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, B \seqar \Delta} |
224 |
& |
225 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma, A_1\laand A_2 \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A_i \seqar \Delta} |
226 |
& |
227 |
%\vlinf{\lefrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma, A\laand B \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, B \seqar \Delta} |
228 |
%\quad |
229 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A1\laor A_2}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A_i} |
230 |
& |
231 |
%\vlinf{\rigrul{\laor}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A\laor B}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, B} |
232 |
%\quad |
233 |
\vliinf{\rigrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A \laand B }{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, B} |
234 |
\\ |
235 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
236 |
%\text{Exponentials:} & & & \\ |
237 |
%\noalign{\bigskip} |
238 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{?}}{}{!\Gamma, ?A \seqar ?\Delta}{!\Gamma , A \seqar ?\Delta} |
239 |
& |
240 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{!}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A \seqar \Delta} |
241 |
& |
242 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{?}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A} |
243 |
& |
244 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{!}}{}{!\Gamma \seqar ?\Delta, ?A}{!\Gamma \seqar ?\Delta, A} |
245 |
\\ |
246 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
247 |
%\text{Structural:} & & & \\ |
248 |
%\noalign{\bigskip} |
249 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta} |
250 |
& |
251 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\cntr}}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, !A, !A \seqar \Delta} |
252 |
& |
253 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\wk}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A }{\Gamma \seqar \Delta} |
254 |
& |
255 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\cntr}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A, ?A} |
256 |
\\ |
257 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
258 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\exists}}{}{\Gamma, \exists x . A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A(a) \seqar \Delta} |
259 |
& |
260 |
\vlinf{\lefrul{\forall}}{}{\Gamma, \forall x. A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A(t) \seqar \Delta} |
261 |
& |
262 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\exists}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, \exists x . A(x)}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A(t)} |
263 |
& |
264 |
\vlinf{\rigrul{\forall}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, \forall x . A(x)}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A(a) } |
265 |
\end{array} |
266 |
\end{array} |
267 |
\] |
268 |
where $p$ atomic, $i \in \{ 1,2 \}$ and the eigenvariable $a$ does not occur free in $\Gamma$ or $\Delta$. |
269 |
\end{definition} |
270 |
|
271 |
|
272 |
\subsection{Deduction theorem} |
273 |
|
274 |
[cite Avron:`semantics and proof theory of linear logic'] |
275 |
|
276 |
We will make much use of the deduction theorem, allowing us to argue informally within a theory for hypotheses that have been promoted. |
277 |
|
278 |
\begin{theorem} |
279 |
[Deduction] |
280 |
If $\mathcal T , A \proves B$ then $\mathcal{T} \proves !A \limp B$. |
281 |
\end{theorem} |
282 |
|
283 |
\todo{need that $A$ above is closed! Check for rules to axioms.} |
284 |
|
285 |
|
286 |
|
287 |
\subsection{Converting axioms to rules in $\MELLW$} |
288 |
|
289 |
\begin{proposition} |
290 |
An axiom $\Ax$ of the form, |
291 |
\[ |
292 |
A_1 \limp \vldots \limp A_m \limp !B_1 \limp \vldots \limp !B_n \limp C |
293 |
\] |
294 |
is equivalent (over propositional $\LL$) to the rule $\Rl$: |
295 |
\[ |
296 |
\vliiinf{\Rl}{}{ !\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ? \Delta }{ !\Gamma \seqar B_1 , ?\Delta }{\vldots }{ !\Gamma \seqar B_n , ?\Delta} |
297 |
\] |
298 |
\end{proposition} |
299 |
\begin{proof} |
300 |
Let us first assume $\Ax$ and derive $\Rl$. From the axiom and Currying, we have a proof of: |
301 |
\begin{equation}\label{eqn:curried-axiom} |
302 |
A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C |
303 |
\end{equation} |
304 |
|
305 |
This can simply be cut against each of the premisses of $\Rl$, applying appropriate contractions and necessitations, to derive it: |
306 |
\[ |
307 |
\vlderivation{ |
308 |
\vliq{c}{}{!\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ?\Delta }{ |
309 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{!\Gamma, \dots , !\Gamma , A_1 , \dots , A_m \seqar C , ?\Delta, \dots , ?\Delta }{ |
310 |
\vlin{!}{}{!\Gamma \seqar !B_n, ?\Delta }{\vlhy{!\Gamma \seqar B_n , ?\Delta }} |
311 |
}{ |
312 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\qquad \qquad \qquad \qquad \vlvdots \qquad \qquad \qquad \qquad }{ |
313 |
\vlin{!}{}{!\Gamma \seqar !B_1 , ?\Delta}{\vlhy{!\Gamma \seqar B_1, ?\Delta }} |
314 |
}{\vlhy{ A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C } } |
315 |
} |
316 |
} |
317 |
} |
318 |
\] |
319 |
|
320 |
Now let us prove $\Ax$ (again in the form of \eqref{eqn:curried-axiom}) by using $\Rl$ as follows: |
321 |
\[ |
322 |
\vliiinf{\Rl}{}{ A_1 , \dots , A_m , !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar C }{ \vlderivation{ |
323 |
\vlin{w}{}{ !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar B_1 }{ |
324 |
\vlin{!}{}{!B_1 \seqar B_1 }{ |
325 |
\vlin{\id}{}{B_1 \seqar B_1 }{\vlhy{}} |
326 |
} |
327 |
} |
328 |
} }{\vldots}{ |
329 |
\vlderivation{ |
330 |
\vlin{w}{}{ !B_1 , \dots , !B_n \seqar B_n }{ |
331 |
\vlin{!}{}{!B_n \seqar B_n }{ |
332 |
\vlin{\id}{}{B_n \seqar B_n }{\vlhy{}} |
333 |
} |
334 |
} |
335 |
} |
336 |
} |
337 |
\] |
338 |
\end{proof} |
339 |
|
340 |
|
341 |
\textbf{NB:} The proof does not strictly require side formulae $? \Delta$ on the right of the sequent arrow $\seqar$, it would work without them, e.g.\ for the intuitionistic case. In a one-sided setting there is no difference. |
342 |
|
343 |
|
344 |
|
345 |
\begin{corollary} |
346 |
The induction axiom of $A^1_2$ is equivalent to the rule: |
347 |
\[ |
348 |
\vliinf{}{(x \notin \FV(\Gamma, \Delta))}{ !\Gamma , A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t) , ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma , A(x) \seqar A(s_0 x ), ?\Delta }{ !\Gamma, A(x) \seqar A( s_1 x ) , ?\Delta} |
349 |
\] |
350 |
\end{corollary} |
351 |
\begin{proof} |
352 |
By proposition above, generalisation and Currying. |
353 |
\end{proof} |
354 |
|
355 |
|
356 |
\subsection{Prenexing} |
357 |
%In the presence of weakening we have a prenex normal form due to the following: |
358 |
% |
359 |
%\[ |
360 |
%\vlderivation{ |
361 |
% \vlin{}{}{\exists x . A \lor B \seqar \exists x . (A(x) \lor B) }{ |
362 |
% |
363 |
% } |
364 |
% } |
365 |
%\] |
366 |
|
367 |
Cannot derive prenexing operations, e.g.\ a problem with $\exists x . A \lor B \seqar \exists x . (A(x) \lor B)$. Can safely add prenexing rules? Or not a problem due to Witness predicate? |
368 |
|
369 |
\section{Free-cut elimination in linear logic} |
370 |
|
371 |
|
372 |
\todo{patrick} |
373 |
|
374 |
\anupam{Possibly need to include the cases for affine logic too, e.g.\ if weakening is native, since it does not play nice as an axiom.} |
375 |
|
376 |
\section{Some variants of arithmetic in linear logic} |
377 |
|
378 |
For pretty much all variants discussed we will actually work in the \emph{affine} variant of linear logic, which validates weakening: $(A \land B )\limp A$. There are many reasons for this; essentially it has not much effect on complexity while also creating a more robust proof theory. For example it induces the following equivalence: |
379 |
\[ |
380 |
!(A\land B) \equiv (!A \land !B) |
381 |
\] |
382 |
(The right-left direction is already valid in usual linear logic, but the left-right direction requires weakening). |
383 |
|
384 |
We define a variant of arithmetic inspired by Bellantoni and Hofmann's $A^1_2$. We describe later some connections to bounded arithmetic. |
385 |
|
386 |
|
387 |
\subsection{Based on Bellantoni-Hoffmann, Leivant, etc.} |
388 |
|
389 |
\newcommand{\natcntr}{\nat\mathit{cntr}} |
390 |
\newcommand{\geneps}{\nat_{\epsilon}} |
391 |
\newcommand{\genzer}{\nat_{0}} |
392 |
\newcommand{\genone}{\nat_{1}} |
393 |
|
394 |
|
395 |
\newcommand{\sepeps}{\epsilon} |
396 |
\newcommand{\sepzer}{\succ_{0}} |
397 |
\newcommand{\sepone}{\succ_{1}} |
398 |
|
399 |
\newcommand{\inj}{\mathit{inj}} |
400 |
\newcommand{\surj}{\mathit{surj}} |
401 |
|
402 |
\begin{definition} |
403 |
[Arithmetic] |
404 |
We have the following axioms: |
405 |
\[ |
406 |
\begin{array}{rl} |
407 |
\wk & (A \land B )\limp A \\ |
408 |
\natcntr & \forall x^N . (N(x) \land N(x)) \\ |
409 |
\geneps & \nat(\epsilon) \\ |
410 |
\genzer & \forall x^N . N(\succ_0 x) \\ |
411 |
\genone & \forall x^N . N(\succ_1 x) \\ |
412 |
\sepeps & \forall x^N . (\epsilon \neq \succ_0 x \land \epsilon \neq \succ_1 x) \\ |
413 |
\sepzer & \forall x^N , y^N. ( \succ_0 x = \succ_0 y \limp x=y ) \\ |
414 |
\sepone & \forall x^N , y^N. ( \succ_1 x = \succ_1 y \limp x=y ) \\ |
415 |
\inj & \forall x^N . \succ_0 x \neq \succ_1 x \\ |
416 |
\surj & \forall x^N . (x = \epsilon \lor \exists y^N . x = \succ_0 y \lor \exists y^N . x = \succ_1 y ) \\ |
417 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
418 |
\ind & A(\epsilon) \limp !( \forall x^{!\nat} . ( A(x) \limp A(\succ_0 x) ) ) \limp !( \forall x^{!\nat} . ( A(x) \limp A(\succ_1 x) ) ) \limp \forall x^{!\nat} . A(x) |
419 |
\end{array} |
420 |
\] |
421 |
|
422 |
Induction rule should be the following, to take account of relativised quantifiers? |
423 |
\[ |
424 |
\vliinf{\ind}{}{ !N(t) , !\Gamma , A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t), ?\Delta }{ !N(a) , !\Gamma, A(a) \seqar A(\succ_0 a) , ?\Delta }{ !N(a) , !\Gamma, A(a) \seqar A(\succ_0 a) , ?\Delta } |
425 |
\] |
426 |
|
427 |
\todo{in existential above, is there a prenexing problem?} |
428 |
|
429 |
\todo{what about $\leq$? Introducing this could solve prenexing problem, e.g.\ by induction?} |
430 |
\end{definition} |
431 |
|
432 |
\subsection{$\nat$-hierarchy} |
433 |
|
434 |
\begin{definition} |
435 |
|
436 |
\todo{replace N with nat.} |
437 |
|
438 |
Let us define the quantifiers $\exists x^N . A$ and $\forall x^N . A$ as $\exists x . (N(x) \land A)$ and $\forall x . (N(x) \limp A) $ respectively. |
439 |
|
440 |
We define $\Sigma^N_0 = \Pi^N_0 $ as the class of formulae that are free of quantifiers. For $i\geq 0$ we define: |
441 |
\begin{itemize} |
442 |
\item $\Sigma^N_{i+1}$ is the class of formulae $\exists x^N . A$ where $A \in \Pi^N_i$. |
443 |
\item $\Pi^N_{i+1}$ is the class of formulae $\forall x^N . A$ where $A \in \Sigma^N_i$. |
444 |
\item ($\Delta^N_i$ is the class $\Sigma^N_i \cap \Pi^N_i$.) |
445 |
\end{itemize} |
446 |
\end{definition} |
447 |
|
448 |
\todo{allow closure under positive Boolean operations?} |
449 |
|
450 |
\todo{What about prenexing rules? Should not change provably total functions!} |
451 |
|
452 |
\subsection{Equivalent rule systems} |
453 |
|
454 |
For the quantifiers $\exists x^N $ and $\forall x^N$ we introduce the following rules, which are compatible with free-cut elimination: |
455 |
|
456 |
\[ |
457 |
\begin{array}{cc} |
458 |
\vlinf{}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, \forall x^N . A(x)}{\Gamma, N(a) \seqar \Delta , A(a)} |
459 |
\quad & \quad |
460 |
\vlinf{}{}{\Gamma, N(t),\forall x^N A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, A(t) \seqar \Delta} |
461 |
\\ |
462 |
\noalign{\bigskip} |
463 |
\vlinf{}{}{\Gamma , \exists x^N A(x) \seqar \Delta}{\Gamma, N(a), A(a) \seqar \Delta} |
464 |
\quad &\quad |
465 |
\vlinf{}{}{\Gamma, N(t) \seqar \Delta , \exists x^N . A(x)}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A(t)} |
466 |
\end{array} |
467 |
\] |
468 |
|
469 |
CHECK THESE! |
470 |
|
471 |
\todo{Also include rules for contraction and weakening.} |
472 |
|
473 |
\section{Convergence of Bellantoni-Cook programs} |
474 |
|
475 |
\subsection{Bellantoni-Cook programs} |
476 |
We first recall the notion of safe recursion on notation from BC. TODO |
477 |
|
478 |
\subsection{Convergence in arithmetic} |
479 |
\begin{theorem} |
480 |
[Convergence] |
481 |
If $\Phi(f)$ is an equational specification corresponding to a BC-program defining $f()$, then $\cax{\Sigma^N_1}{\pind} \proves \ !\Phi(f) \limp \forall \vec{x}^{!N} . N(f(\vec x))$. |
482 |
\end{theorem} |
483 |
\begin{proof} |
484 |
We show by induction on the structure of a BC-program for $f(\vec x ; \vec y)$ that: |
485 |
\begin{equation} |
486 |
\Phi(f) , \cax{\Sigma^N_1}{\pind} \proves \ \forall \vec{x}^{!N} . \forall \vec{y}^N . N(f(\vec x ; \vec y)) |
487 |
\end{equation} |
488 |
We give some key cases in what follows. |
489 |
|
490 |
Suppose $f$ is defined by PRN by: |
491 |
\[ |
492 |
\begin{array}{rcl} |
493 |
f(0,\vec x ; \vec y) & = & g(\vec x ; \vec y) \\ |
494 |
f(\succ_i x , \vec x ; \vec y) & = & h_i (x, \vec x ; \vec y , f(x , \vec x ; \vec y)) |
495 |
\end{array} |
496 |
\] |
497 |
By the inductive hypothesis we already have that $g, h_0, h_1$ are provably convergent, so let us suppose that $N(\vec x)$ and prove, |
498 |
\begin{equation} |
499 |
\forall x^{!N} . ( N(\vec y) \limp N(f(x , \vec x ; \vec y) ) |
500 |
\end{equation} |
501 |
by $\cax{\Sigma^N_1}{\pind}$ on $x$. |
502 |
|
503 |
In the base case we have the following proof: |
504 |
\[ |
505 |
\vlderivation{ |
506 |
\vliin{}{}{N(\vec y) \limp N(f(0, \vec x ; \vec y))}{ |
507 |
\vltr{IH}{N(\vec y) \limp N(g(\vec x ; \vec y))}{\vlhy{\quad}}{\vlhy{}}{\vlhy{\quad}} |
508 |
}{ |
509 |
\vlin{}{}{N(g (\vec x ; \vec y) ) \limp N(f(0, \vec x ; \vec y)) }{ |
510 |
\vlin{}{}{g(\vec x ; \vec y) = f(0 , \vec x ; \vec y)}{\vlhy{}} |
511 |
} |
512 |
} |
513 |
} |
514 |
\] |
515 |
|
516 |
For the inductive step, we need to show that, |
517 |
\[ |
518 |
\forall x^{!N} . (( N(\vec y) \limp N( f(x, \vec x ; \vec y) ) ) \limp N(\vec y) \limp N(f(\succ_i x , \vec x ; \vec y) ) ) |
519 |
\] |
520 |
so let us suppose that $N(x)$ and we give the following proof: |
521 |
\[ |
522 |
\vlderivation{ |
523 |
\vlin{N\cntr}{}{N(y) \limp ( N(y ) \limp N(f( x , \vec x ; \vec y ) ) ) \limp N(f (\succ_i x , \vec x ; \vec y) ) }{ |
524 |
\vliin{}{}{N(y) \limp N(y) \limp ( N(y ) \limp N(f( x , \vec x ; \vec y ) ) ) \limp N(f (\succ_i x , \vec x ; \vec y) ) }{ |
525 |
\vliin{}{}{ N(y) \limp N(y) \limp ( N(y) \limp N( f(x, \vec x ; \vec y) ) ) \limp N( h_i (x , \vec x ; \vec y , f(x , \vec x ; \vec y) ) ) }{ |
526 |
\vltr{MLL}{( N(\vec y) \limp (N (\vec y) \limp N(f(x, \vec x ; \vec y) )) \limp N(f(x, \vec x ; \vec y)) }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{\ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
527 |
}{ |
528 |
\vlhy{2} |
529 |
} |
530 |
}{ |
531 |
\vlhy{3} |
532 |
} |
533 |
} |
534 |
} |
535 |
\] |
536 |
TOFINISH |
537 |
\end{proof} |
538 |
|
539 |
\section{Witness function method} |
540 |
|
541 |
\todo{negation normal form} |
542 |
|
543 |
\newcommand{\type}{\mathtt{t}} |
544 |
\newcommand{\norm}{\nu} |
545 |
\newcommand{\safe}{\sigma} |
546 |
|
547 |
\subsection{Typing} |
548 |
|
549 |
\begin{definition} |
550 |
[Types] |
551 |
To each formula we associate a tuple type as follows: |
552 |
\[ |
553 |
\begin{array}{rcll} |
554 |
\type (\nat (t)) & := & \Nat & \\ |
555 |
\type(s = t) & := & \Nat & \\ |
556 |
\type (A \star B) & : = & \type (A) \times \type (B) & \text{for $\star \in \{ \lor, \land, \laor, \laand \} $.} \\ |
557 |
\type (! A) & : = & \type_\norm (A) & \\ |
558 |
\type (\exists x^N . A) & := & \Nat \times \type (A) & \\ |
559 |
% \type (\forall x^N . A) & := & \Nat \to \type(A) |
560 |
\end{array} |
561 |
\] |
562 |
where $\nu$ designates that the inputs are normal. |
563 |
\end{definition} |
564 |
|
565 |
\todo{compatibility with safety. To consider.} |
566 |
|
567 |
|
568 |
|
569 |
|
570 |
\newcommand{\witness}[2]{\mathit{Witness}^{#1}_{#2}} |
571 |
\begin{definition} |
572 |
[Witness predicate] |
573 |
We define the following formula: |
574 |
\[ |
575 |
\begin{array}{rcll} |
576 |
\witness{\vec a}{A} (w, \vec a) & := & A(\vec a) & \text{for $A$ quantifier-free.} \\ |
577 |
\witness{\vec a}{\exists x . A} (w, \vec w , \vec a) & := & \witness{\vec{a}, a}{A(a)}(\vec w , \vec a, w ) & \\ |
578 |
\witness{\vec a}{A \star B} ( \vec w^1 , \vec w^2 ) & := & \witness{\vec a}{A} (\vec w^1) \star \witness{\vec a}{B} (\vec w^2) & \text{for $\star \in \{ \land, \lor, \laand , \laor\}$.} \\ |
579 |
\end{array} |
580 |
\] |
581 |
\end{definition} |
582 |
\todo{problem: what about complexity of checking equality? } |
583 |
|
584 |
\todo{What about $\nat (t)$? What does it mean? Replace with true?} |
585 |
|
586 |
\todo{either use the witness predicate above, or use realizability predicate at meta-level and a model theory, like BH.} |
587 |
|
588 |
\anupam{Need to check above properly. $N(t)$ should be witnessed by the value of $t $ in the model. For equality of terms the witness should not do anything.} |
589 |
|
590 |
\subsection{The translation} |
591 |
Need witness predicate so that we know what is being preserved. |
592 |
|
593 |
\begin{definition} |
594 |
[Translation] |
595 |
We give a translation of proofs $\pi$ of sequents $\Gamma(\vec a) \seqar \Delta(\vec a)$ to BC-programs for a vector of functions $\vec f^\pi : \type(\bigotimes\Gamma) \times \Nat^{|\vec a|} \to \type(\bigparr\Delta)$ such that: |
596 |
\[ |
597 |
\witness{\vec a}{\bigotimes \Gamma} (\vec w , \vec a) \implies \witness{\vec a}{\bigparr \Delta } (\vec f(\vec w , \vec a), \vec a) |
598 |
\] |
599 |
We will be explicit about normal and safe inputs when necessary, for the most part we will simply rearrange inputs into lists $(\vec x; \vec a)$ as in BC framework. |
600 |
|
601 |
We often suppress the parameters $\vec a$ when it is not important. |
602 |
|
603 |
\anupam{Is this implication provable in Bellantoni's version of PV based on BC?} |
604 |
|
605 |
\anupam{for moment try ignore decoration on right? what about negation?} |
606 |
|
607 |
|
608 |
|
609 |
\[ |
610 |
\vlderivation{ |
611 |
\vliin{\land}{}{ \Gamma, \Sigma \seqar \Delta, \Pi, A\land B }{ |
612 |
\vltr{\pi_1}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
613 |
}{ |
614 |
\vltr{\pi_2}{ \Sigma \seqar \Pi, B }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
615 |
} |
616 |
} |
617 |
\] |
618 |
|
619 |
So we have $\vec f^{1} (\vec x ; \vec a)$ and $\vec f^2 (\vec y ; \vec b)$ for $\pi_1 $ and $\pi_2$ respectively, by the inductive hypothesis. We simply construct $\vec f^\pi$ by rearranging these functions: |
620 |
\[ |
621 |
\vec f^\pi (\vec x , \vec y ; \vec a , \vec b) \quad := \quad ( f^1_1 (\vec x ; \vec a) , \dots , f^1_{|\Delta|} (\vec x ; \vec a) , f^2_1 (\vec y; \vec b) , \dots , f^2_{|\Pi|} (\vec y ; \vec b) , f^1_{|\Delta|+1} (\vec x ; \vec a ) , f^2_{|\Pi|+1} (\vec y ; \vec b) |
622 |
\] |
623 |
|
624 |
\anupam{bad notation since need to include free variables of sequent too. (also of theory.) Reconsider.} |
625 |
|
626 |
\[ |
627 |
\vlderivation{ |
628 |
\vlin{\lefrul{\cntr}}{}{ !A , \Gamma \seqar \Delta }{ |
629 |
\vltr{\pi'}{ !A, !A , \Gamma \seqar \Delta}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
630 |
} |
631 |
} |
632 |
\] |
633 |
Have $\vec f' (x_1 , x_2 , \vec y ; \vec a)$ for $\pi'$. Define |
634 |
\[ |
635 |
\vec f (x_1 , \vec y ; \vec a) \quad := \quad \vec f'(x_1 , x_1 , \vec y ; \vec a) |
636 |
\] |
637 |
\[ |
638 |
\vlderivation{ |
639 |
\vlin{\rigrul{\cntr}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A}{ |
640 |
\vltr{\pi'}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, ?A, ?A}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
641 |
} |
642 |
} |
643 |
\] |
644 |
(need test function against witness predicate?) |
645 |
|
646 |
\anupam{problem: how to test even equality of two terms? Maybe treat $?$ as $!$ on left?} |
647 |
|
648 |
\anupam{Not a problem by free-cut elimination! Can assume there are no $?$ in the proof! Is this equivalent to treaing $?$ as $!$ on left?} |
649 |
|
650 |
\anupam{Yes I think so. We can work in a left-sided calculus. only problem is for induction. But this can never be a problem for modalities since induction formulae are modality-free.} |
651 |
|
652 |
\anupam{this is actually the main point.} |
653 |
|
654 |
|
655 |
\[ |
656 |
\vlderivation{ |
657 |
\vliin{\rigrul{\laand}}{}{\Gamma \seqar \Delta, A \laand B}{ |
658 |
\vltr{\pi_1}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
659 |
}{ |
660 |
\vltr{\pi_2}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, B}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
661 |
} |
662 |
} |
663 |
\] |
664 |
|
665 |
Suppose we have $\vec f^i (\vec x , \vec a ; \vec y , \vec b)$ from $\pi_i$. |
666 |
|
667 |
\anupam{problem: does this require many tests, just like for contraction? Can we isolate a different complexity class? e.g.\ PH or Grzegorzyck?} |
668 |
\anupam{skip this case and consider later.} |
669 |
\[ |
670 |
\vlderivation{ |
671 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma , \Sigma \seqar \Delta , \Pi}{ |
672 |
\vltr{\pi_1}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta, A }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
673 |
}{ |
674 |
\vltr{\pi_2}{\Sigma , A \seqar \Pi}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
675 |
} |
676 |
} |
677 |
\] |
678 |
|
679 |
We can assume that $A$ in the conclusion of $\pi_2$ is free of modalities, since one of the $A$s must be directly descended from an induction formula, and so consists of only safe inputs. Therefore we have functions $\vec f^1 (\vec w; \vec x)$ and $\vec f^2 (\vec y ; \vec z , \vec u)$ for $\pi_1$ and $\pi_2 $ respectively (free variable parameters are suppressed), with $\vec u$ corresponding to the (safe) inputs for $A$. |
680 |
|
681 |
Let us write: |
682 |
\[ |
683 |
\begin{array}{rcl} |
684 |
\vec f^1 & = & ( \vec f^1_i )^{|\Delta|+1}_{i=1} \\ |
685 |
\vec f^2 & = & ( \vec f^2_i )^{|\Pi|}_{i=1} |
686 |
\end{array} |
687 |
\] |
688 |
to denote the parts of $\vec f^i$ corresponding to formulae in their sequents. |
689 |
|
690 |
|
691 |
We define: |
692 |
\[ |
693 |
\vec f (\vec w , \vec y ; \vec x , \vec z) |
694 |
\quad := \quad |
695 |
( |
696 |
( \vec f^1_i (\vec w ; \vec x) )_{i \leq |\Delta|} |
697 |
, |
698 |
\vec f^2 ( \vec y ; \vec z , \vec f^1_{|\Delta| +1 } (\vec w ; \vec x) ) |
699 |
) |
700 |
\] |
701 |
|
702 |
Notice that all safe inputs are hereditarily right of a $;$, and so these terms are definable by safe composition and projection. |
703 |
|
704 |
\todo{another case for $!\nat(x)$ cut formula.} |
705 |
|
706 |
\anupam{should work for arbitrary $!$-cuts due to principal case for $!$} |
707 |
|
708 |
|
709 |
Right existential: |
710 |
\[ |
711 |
\vlderivation{ |
712 |
\vlin{\rigrul{\exists}}{}{ \Gamma, \nat(t) \seqar \Delta , \exists x^\nat . A(x) }{ |
713 |
\vltr{\pi'}{ \Gamma \seqar \Delta , A(t) }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
714 |
} |
715 |
} |
716 |
\] |
717 |
Suppose we have functions $\vec f^X (\vec x ; \vec y)$ from $\pi'$ for $X = \Delta$ or $ X=A$. |
718 |
\[ |
719 |
\vec f(\vec x ; \vec y , z) \quad := \quad ( \vec f^\Delta (\vec x ; \vec y) , z , \vec f^A ( \vec x ; \vec y ) ) |
720 |
\] |
721 |
|
722 |
|
723 |
Left existential: |
724 |
\[ |
725 |
\vlderivation{ |
726 |
\vlin{\lefrul{\exists}}{}{ \Gamma, \exists x^N . A(x) \seqar \Delta }{ |
727 |
\vltr{\pi'(a)}{ \Gamma, N(a) , A(a) \seqar \Delta }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
728 |
} |
729 |
} |
730 |
\] |
731 |
|
732 |
Suppose we have functions $\vec f' (\vec u , \vec v ; x , \vec y , \vec z)$ from $\pi'$ with $(\vec u ; \vec x )$ corresponding to $\Gamma$, $(;x)$ corresponding to $N(a)$ and $(\vec v ; \vec z)$ corresponding to $A(a)$. We define: |
733 |
\[ |
734 |
\vec f ( \vec u , \vec v ; ) |
735 |
\] |
736 |
|
737 |
\anupam{should just be same, no? To consider.} |
738 |
|
739 |
%Suppose we have functions $\vec g (\vec v , \vec w ; \vec x , y , \vec z)$ where $(\vec v ; \vec x) $ corresponds to $\Gamma$, $y$ corresponds to $\nat(a)$ and $(\vec w ; \vec z) $ corresponds to $A(a)$. Then we define: |
740 |
%\[ |
741 |
%\vec f ( \vec v , \vec w ; \vec x , y , \vec z ) |
742 |
%\] |
743 |
|
744 |
\todo{finish} |
745 |
|
746 |
!: |
747 |
\[ |
748 |
\vlderivation{ |
749 |
\vlin{!}{}{\Gamma, !A \seqar \Delta}{ |
750 |
\vltr{\pi'}{ \Gamma , A \seqar \Delta }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
751 |
} |
752 |
} |
753 |
\] |
754 |
\anupam{Again, use free-cut elimination to get rid of this case. We know $!$-ed formulae in advance, so just fix those as normal inputs in advance.} |
755 |
|
756 |
|
757 |
Induction: (can assume no side-formulae on right for same reason as no contraction.) |
758 |
\[ |
759 |
\vlderivation{ |
760 |
\vliin{\ind}{}{ !\Gamma , !\nat (t) , A(\epsilon) \seqar A(t) }{ |
761 |
\vltr{\pi_0}{ !\Gamma , !\nat(a) , A(a) \seqar A(\succ_0 a)}{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
762 |
}{ |
763 |
\vltr{\pi_1}{ !\Gamma , !\nat(a), A(a)\seqar A(\succ_1 a) }{\vlhy{\quad }}{\vlhy{ }}{\vlhy{\quad }} |
764 |
} |
765 |
} |
766 |
\] |
767 |
|
768 |
Suppose we have functions $\vec f^i (\vec x , y ; \vec u)$ from proofs $\pi_i$ where $\vec x $ corresponds to $!\Gamma$, $y$ corresponds to $!N(a)$ and $\vec u$ corresponds to $A(a)$. |
769 |
|
770 |
|
771 |
\anupam{role of $!N(a)$ versus having $a$ as a parameter to function. To consider!} |
772 |
|
773 |
Define the function $f_k$ (for $k = 1 , \dots , |\vec u|$) by PRN: |
774 |
\[ |
775 |
\begin{array}{rcl} |
776 |
f_k(\epsilon, \vec x , y ; \vec u) & := & u_k \\ |
777 |
f_k (\succ_i w , \vec x , y ; \vec u) & : = & f^i_k ( \vec x , y ; \vec f ( w, \vec x , y ; \vec u ) ) |
778 |
\end{array} |
779 |
\] |
780 |
|
781 |
\anupam{check this, esp use of parameters, cf.\ above.} |
782 |
|
783 |
\anupam{Is this not using a simultaneous version of PRN? Might need concatenation of words/basic coding to deal with this.} |
784 |
|
785 |
|
786 |
\end{definition} |
787 |
|
788 |
\newcommand{\concat}{\mathit{concat}} |
789 |
\paragraph{Some points on concatenation \anupam{if necessary}} |
790 |
We can define the concatenation operation by PRN: |
791 |
\[ |
792 |
\begin{array}{rcl} |
793 |
\concat (\epsilon ; y) & : = & x \\ |
794 |
\concat (\succ_i x ; y) & := & \succ_i \concat (x ; y) |
795 |
\end{array} |
796 |
\] |
797 |
|
798 |
From here we can define iterated concatenation: |
799 |
\[ |
800 |
\concat (x_1 , \dots x_n ; y) \quad := \quad \concat (x_n ; \concat (x_{n-1} ; \vldots \concat (x_1 ; y) \vldots ) ) |
801 |
\] |
802 |
|
803 |
(notice all safe inputs are hereditarily to the right of $;$ so this is definable by safe composition and projection.) |
804 |
|
805 |
\section{Further work} |
806 |
|
807 |
Say something about minimisation and the polynomial hierarchy. Could be achieved by controlling contraction/additives, since this requires a notion of tests. |
808 |
|
809 |
\section{Conclusions} |
810 |
|
811 |
\appendix |
812 |
|
813 |
\section{Some cut-elimination cases} |
814 |
We work in a one-sided calculus for full linear logic. When working in the affine setting we simply drop the condition that weakened formulae are $?$-ed. |
815 |
|
816 |
As well as all usual rules, we have the induction rule: |
817 |
\[ |
818 |
\vlinf{\indr}{(x \notin FV (\Gamma) )}{? \Gamma, A^\perp (0) , A(t)}{? \Gamma , A^\perp (x) , A(s x) } |
819 |
\] |
820 |
|
821 |
We give all the various cut-reduction cases in the following section but first we give a simple cut-elimination argument. |
822 |
|
823 |
\subsection{A basic (free-)cut elimination argument} |
824 |
We give an argument that easily scales to free-cut elimination, i.e.\ in the presence of non-logical rules. |
825 |
|
826 |
\newcommand{\anarrow}[2]{\overset{#1}{\underset{#2}{\longrightarrow}}} |
827 |
\newcommand{\cutredlin}{\mathit{ma}} |
828 |
\newcommand{\cutredexp}{exp} |
829 |
|
830 |
\begin{definition} |
831 |
Let $\anarrow{}{\cutredexp}$ denote the reduction steps concerning exponential cuts, and $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$ be the set of cut-reduction steps concerning multiplicative and additive cuts. |
832 |
\end{definition} |
833 |
|
834 |
\newcommand{\rk}{\mathsf{rk}} |
835 |
\renewcommand{\deg}{\mathsf{deg}} |
836 |
\begin{definition} |
837 |
[Measures] |
838 |
For a $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$-redex $r$, let its \emph{degree} $\deg( r)$ be the number of logical connectives or quantifiers in its cut-formula. For a proof $\pi$, its \emph{degree} $\deg( \pi)$ is the multiset of the degree of its redexes. |
839 |
\end{definition} |
840 |
|
841 |
\begin{proposition} |
842 |
If $\pi$ is not $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$-normal then there is a derivation $L:\pi \anarrow{*}{\cutredlin} \pi'$ such that $\deg(\pi')< \deg(\pi)$. |
843 |
\end{proposition} |
844 |
\begin{proof} |
845 |
First let us show the statement in the special case that $\pi$ contains precisely one $\cut$-inference as its final step, by induction on $|\pi|$. Each commutative $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$-step results in us being able to apply the inductive hypothesis to smaller proofs,- in the case of $\vlan $ two smaller proofs. Each key $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$-case strictly reduces the degree of the proof. Consequently we can eventually transform $\pi$ to a proof $\pi'$ which has possibly several cuts of smaller degree, as required. |
846 |
|
847 |
Now to the general case, we simply apply the above procedure to the subproof above a topmost cut in $\pi$. |
848 |
\end{proof} |
849 |
\begin{corollary} |
850 |
$\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$ is weakly normalising. |
851 |
\end{corollary} |
852 |
|
853 |
|
854 |
\newcommand{\cntdown}{\mathit{cn}} |
855 |
\begin{definition} |
856 |
[Lazy contraction] |
857 |
Let $\anarrow{}{\cntdown}$ comprise of the following reduction steps: |
858 |
\begin{enumerate} |
859 |
\item The commuting steps, |
860 |
\[ |
861 |
\vlderivation{ |
862 |
\vlin{\rho}{}{\Gamma', ?A, }{ |
863 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ? A, ? A}} |
864 |
} |
865 |
} |
866 |
\quad\to \quad |
867 |
\vlderivation{ |
868 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma', ?A}{ |
869 |
\vlin{\rho}{}{\Gamma', ?A, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ? A, ? A}} |
870 |
} |
871 |
} |
872 |
\] |
873 |
for each unary rule $\rho$. |
874 |
\item |
875 |
The key steps: |
876 |
\[ |
877 |
\begin{array}{rcl} |
878 |
\vlderivation{ |
879 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A}{ |
880 |
\vlin{\wk}{}{\Gamma, ?A, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A}} |
881 |
} |
882 |
} |
883 |
\quad &\to & \quad |
884 |
\Gamma, ?A |
885 |
% \] |
886 |
% and |
887 |
% \[ |
888 |
\\ |
889 |
\noalign{\smallskip} |
890 |
\vlderivation{ |
891 |
\vlin{\wk}{}{\Gamma, ?A, ?A}{ |
892 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A}} |
893 |
} |
894 |
} |
895 |
\quad &\to& \quad |
896 |
\Gamma, ?A, ?A |
897 |
\end{array} |
898 |
\]. |
899 |
\item The commuting steps, |
900 |
\[ |
901 |
\vlderivation{ |
902 |
\vliin{\rho}{}{\Gamma ,?A}{ |
903 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma_1, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma_1, ?A, ?A}} |
904 |
}{\vlhy{\Gamma_2}} |
905 |
} |
906 |
\quad \to \quad |
907 |
\vlderivation{ |
908 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A}{ |
909 |
\vliin{\rho}{}{\Gamma,?A, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma_1, ?A, ?A}}{ \vlhy{\Gamma_2} } |
910 |
} |
911 |
} |
912 |
\] |
913 |
%\[ |
914 |
%\begin{array}{rcl} |
915 |
% \vlderivation{ |
916 |
% \vliin{\land}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A, B\land C}{ |
917 |
% \vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A, B}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}} |
918 |
% }{\vlhy{\Delta, C}} |
919 |
% } |
920 |
% \quad &\to &\quad |
921 |
% \vlderivation{ |
922 |
% \vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A, B\land C}{ |
923 |
% \vliin{\land}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A, ?A, B\land C}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}}{ \vlhy{\Delta, C} } |
924 |
% } |
925 |
% } |
926 |
%% \] |
927 |
%% |
928 |
%% \[ |
929 |
%\\ |
930 |
%\noalign{\smallskip} |
931 |
% \vlderivation{ |
932 |
% \vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A}{ |
933 |
% \vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A, B}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}} |
934 |
% }{\vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{B}}} |
935 |
% } |
936 |
% \quad &\to& \quad |
937 |
% \vlderivation{ |
938 |
% \vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A}{ |
939 |
% \vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, ?A, ?A}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}}{ \vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{B}} } |
940 |
% } |
941 |
% } |
942 |
%\end{array} |
943 |
%\] |
944 |
for each binary rule $\rho \in \{ \land, \cut \}$. |
945 |
\item The commuting step: |
946 |
\[ |
947 |
\vlderivation{ |
948 |
\vliin{\vlan}{}{\Gamma, ?A, B\vlan C}{ |
949 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A, B}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}} |
950 |
}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, B}} |
951 |
} |
952 |
\quad \to \quad |
953 |
\vlderivation{ |
954 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{\Gamma, ?A, B\vlan C}{ |
955 |
\vliin{\vlan}{}{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B\vlan C}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, B}}{ |
956 |
\vlin{\wk}{}{\Gamma, ?A, ?A, C}{\vlhy{\Gamma, ?A, C}} |
957 |
} |
958 |
} |
959 |
} |
960 |
\] |
961 |
\end{enumerate} |
962 |
For binary rules: |
963 |
|
964 |
\end{definition} |
965 |
\begin{proposition} |
966 |
$\anarrow{}{\cntdown}$ is weakly normalising |
967 |
, modulo $\cntr$-$\cntr$ redexes, |
968 |
and degree-preserving. |
969 |
If $\pi$ is $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$-normal and $\pi \downarrow_\cntdown \pi'$, then so is $\pi'$. |
970 |
\end{proposition} |
971 |
\begin{proof} |
972 |
By induction on the number of redexes in a proof. Start with bottommost redex, by induction on number of inference steps beneath it. |
973 |
\end{proof} |
974 |
|
975 |
\begin{remark} |
976 |
Only weakly normalising since $\cntr$ can commute with $\cntr$, allowing cycles. |
977 |
\end{remark} |
978 |
|
979 |
\begin{proposition} |
980 |
If $\pi$ is $\anarrow{}{\cutredexp}$-reducible but $\anarrow{}{\cutredlin}$- and $\anarrow{}{\cntdown}$-normal then there is a derivation $H:\pi \anarrow{*}{\cutredexp} \pi'$ such that $\deg (\pi')<\deg(\pi)$. |
981 |
\end{proposition} |
982 |
|
983 |
|
984 |
|
985 |
\subsection{Base cases} |
986 |
|
987 |
\[ |
988 |
\vlderivation{ |
989 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,a }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,a} }{ \vlin{\id}{}{a,a^\bot}{ \vlhy{} } } |
990 |
} |
991 |
\quad\to\quad |
992 |
\vlderivation{ |
993 |
\Gamma,a |
994 |
} |
995 |
\] |
996 |
|
997 |
\[ |
998 |
\vlderivation{ |
999 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma}{ \vlin{\bot}{}{ \Gamma,\bot }{ \vlhy{\Gamma} } }{ \vlin{1}{}{1}{ \vlhy{} } } |
1000 |
} |
1001 |
\quad\to\quad |
1002 |
\vlderivation{ |
1003 |
\Gamma |
1004 |
} |
1005 |
\] |
1006 |
|
1007 |
\[ |
1008 |
\vlderivation{ |
1009 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,\top }{ \vlin{\top}{}{ \Gamma,\top,0 }{ \vlhy{} } }{ \vlhy{\Delta , \top } } |
1010 |
} |
1011 |
\quad\to\quad |
1012 |
\vlinf{\top}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,\top }{} |
1013 |
\] |
1014 |
|
1015 |
\subsection{Commutative cases} |
1016 |
These are the cases when the principal formula of a step is not active for the cut-step below. |
1017 |
|
1018 |
\begin{enumerate} |
1019 |
\item The cut-step is immediately preceded by an initial step. Note that only the case for $\top$ applies: |
1020 |
\[ |
1021 |
\vlderivation{ |
1022 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,\top}{ |
1023 |
\vlin{\top}{ }{ \Gamma,\top,A }{ \vlhy{} } |
1024 |
}{ \vlhy{\Delta,A^\bot } } |
1025 |
} |
1026 |
\quad\to\quad |
1027 |
\vlinf{\top}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,\top }{} |
1028 |
\] |
1029 |
%Notice that this commutation eliminates the cut entirely and preserves the height of all cuts below. |
1030 |
\item\label{CaseCommOneStep} A cut-step is immediately preceded by a step $\rho$ with exactly one premiss: |
1031 |
\[ |
1032 |
\vlderivation{ |
1033 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma',\Delta}{\vlin{\rho}{}{\Gamma',A}{\vlhy{\Gamma,A}}}{\vlhy{A^\bot , \Delta}} |
1034 |
} |
1035 |
\] |
1036 |
We have three subcases: |
1037 |
\begin{enumerate} |
1038 |
\item\label{subcase:unary-commutation-vanilla} |
1039 |
%$\Delta$ consists of only $?$-ed formulae or |
1040 |
If $\rho \notin \{! , \indr \}$ then we can simply permute as follows: |
1041 |
\begin{equation} |
1042 |
\label{eqn:com-case-unary-simple} |
1043 |
\vlderivation{ |
1044 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma',\Delta}{\vlin{\rho}{}{\Gamma',A}{\vlhy{\Gamma,A}}}{\vlhy{A^\bot , \Delta}} |
1045 |
} |
1046 |
\quad \to \quad |
1047 |
\vlderivation{ |
1048 |
\vlin{\rho}{}{\Gamma',\Delta}{ |
1049 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma,\Delta}{\vlhy{\Gamma,A}}{\vlhy{A^\bot , \Delta}} |
1050 |
} |
1051 |
} |
1052 |
\end{equation} |
1053 |
(If $\rho$ was $\forall$ then we might need to rename some free variables in $\Delta$.) |
1054 |
\item $\rho $ is a $!$-step. Therefore $\Gamma$ has the form $? \Sigma , B$ and $A$ has the form $?C$, yielding the following situation: |
1055 |
\[ |
1056 |
\vlderivation{ |
1057 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{? \Sigma, !B, \Delta }{ |
1058 |
\vlin{!}{}{? \Sigma, !B , ?C}{\vlhy{?\Sigma , B , ?C} } |
1059 |
}{ |
1060 |
\vlin{\rho'}{}{!C^\perp , \Delta}{\vlhy{\vlvdots}} |
1061 |
} |
1062 |
} |
1063 |
\] |
1064 |
Now, if $!C^\perp$ is principle for $\rho'$ then $\rho'\in \{! , \indr\}$ and so $\Delta $ must be $?$-ed; in this case we are able to apply the transformation \eqref{eqn:com-case-unary-simple}. Otherwise $A^\perp$ is not principal for $\rho'$ and so $\rho' \notin \{! , \indr \}$, which means we can apply \ref{subcase:unary-commutation-vanilla} along this side of the subproof. |
1065 |
\item $\rho$ is a $\indr$-step. Therefore $\Gamma$ has the form $? \Sigma , B^\perp(x), B(s x) $ and $A$ has the form $?C$, and the argument is similar to the case above. |
1066 |
% yielding the following situation: |
1067 |
%\[ |
1068 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1069 |
% \vliin{\cut}{}{? \Sigma, B^\perp (0) , B(t), \Delta }{ |
1070 |
% \vlin{\indr}{}{? \Sigma, B^\perp (0) , B(t) , ?C}{\vlhy{?\Sigma , B^\perp(x) , B(s x) , ?C} } |
1071 |
% }{ |
1072 |
% \vlin{\rho'}{}{!C^\perp , \Delta}{\vlhy{\vlvdots}} |
1073 |
%} |
1074 |
%} |
1075 |
%\] |
1076 |
\end{enumerate} |
1077 |
|
1078 |
|
1079 |
|
1080 |
\item A cut-step is immediately preceded by a $\vlte $-step: |
1081 |
\[ |
1082 |
\vlderivation{ |
1083 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,\Sigma,A\vlte B }{ |
1084 |
\vliin{\vlte}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,A\vlte B,C }{\vlhy{\Gamma,A,C}}{\vlhy{\Delta,B}} |
1085 |
}{\vlhy{ \Sigma , C^\bot }} |
1086 |
} |
1087 |
\quad\to\quad |
1088 |
\vlderivation{ |
1089 |
\vliin{\vlte}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,\Sigma,A\vlte B}{ |
1090 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma,\Sigma,A}{\vlhy{\Gamma,A,C}}{\vlhy{\Sigma,C^\bot}} |
1091 |
}{\vlhy{\Delta,B}} |
1092 |
} |
1093 |
\] |
1094 |
%Notice that this commutation might increase the height of any cuts below along the right branch of the indicated cut, but decreases the height along the left branch. |
1095 |
\item\label{CommCaseAmpersand} A cut-step is immediately preceded by a $\vlan$-step. |
1096 |
\[ |
1097 |
\vlderivation{ |
1098 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,A\vlan B }{ \vliin{\vlan}{}{\Gamma,A\vlan B,C}{ \vlhy{\Gamma,A,C} }{\vlhy{\Gamma,B,C}}}{ \vlhy{\Delta, C^\bot} } |
1099 |
} |
1100 |
\quad\to\quad |
1101 |
\vlderivation{ |
1102 |
\vliin{\vlan}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,A\vlan B }{ |
1103 |
\vliin{cut}{}{\Gamma,\Delta,A }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,A,C} }{ \vlhy{ \Delta,C^\bot } } |
1104 |
}{ |
1105 |
\vliin{ \cut }{}{\Gamma,\Delta,B}{ \vlhy{\Gamma,B,C } }{ \vlhy{\Delta,C^\bot} } |
1106 |
} |
1107 |
} |
1108 |
\] |
1109 |
\item (No rule for cuts commuting with cuts.) |
1110 |
%A cut-step is immediately preceded by another cut-step: |
1111 |
\[ |
1112 |
\vlderivation{ |
1113 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, \Sigma}{ |
1114 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, B}{\vlhy{\Gamma, A}}{\vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{A}, B}} |
1115 |
}{\vlhy{\Sigma, \lnot{B}}} |
1116 |
} |
1117 |
\quad\to\quad |
1118 |
\vlderivation{ |
1119 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta, \Sigma}{\vlhy{\Gamma, A}}{ |
1120 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Delta, \Sigma, \lnot{A}}{\vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{A}, B}}{\vlhy{\Sigma, \lnot{B}}} |
1121 |
} |
1122 |
} |
1123 |
\] |
1124 |
\end{enumerate} |
1125 |
|
1126 |
|
1127 |
|
1128 |
\subsection{Key cases: structural steps} |
1129 |
%[THIS SECTION MIGHT NOT BE NECESSARY] |
1130 |
We attempt to permute cuts on exponential formulae over structural steps whose principal formula is active for the cut. |
1131 |
|
1132 |
We use the commutative case \ref{CaseCommOneStep} to assume that the topmost cut-step in a sequence has already been permuted up to its origin on the $!$-side. |
1133 |
|
1134 |
We have two cases. |
1135 |
\begin{enumerate} |
1136 |
\item\label{StructStepCont} The structural step preceding the cut is a weakening: |
1137 |
\[ |
1138 |
\vlderivation{ |
1139 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{?\Gamma,\Delta}{ \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } }{ \vlin{w}{}{ ?A^\bot }{ \vlhy{\Delta } } } |
1140 |
} |
1141 |
\quad\to\quad |
1142 |
\vlinf{w}{}{?\Gamma,\Delta}{ \Delta } |
1143 |
\] |
1144 |
%\item The structural step preceding the cut is a contraction: |
1145 |
%\[ |
1146 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1147 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,\Delta }{ |
1148 |
% \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1149 |
%}{ \vlin{c}{}{ ?A^\bot , \Delta }{ \vlhy{ ?A^\bot , ?A^\bot , \Delta} } } |
1150 |
%} |
1151 |
%\quad\to\quad |
1152 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1153 |
%\vliq{c}{}{?\Gamma, \Delta}{ |
1154 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{?\Gamma, ?\Gamma,\Delta }{ |
1155 |
% \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1156 |
%}{ |
1157 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{?\Gamma,?A^\bot , \Delta }{ |
1158 |
% \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1159 |
%}{ \vlhy{?A^\bot , ?A^\bot , \Delta } } |
1160 |
%} |
1161 |
%} |
1162 |
%} |
1163 |
%\] |
1164 |
%OR use a multicut: |
1165 |
%\[ |
1166 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1167 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,\Delta }{ |
1168 |
% \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1169 |
%}{ \vlin{c}{}{ ?A^\bot , \Delta }{ \vlhy{ ?A^\bot , ?A^\bot , \Delta} } } |
1170 |
%} |
1171 |
%\quad\to\quad |
1172 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1173 |
%\vliin{\multicut}{}{?\Gamma,?A^\bot , \Delta }{ |
1174 |
% \vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1175 |
%}{ \vlhy{?A^\bot , ?A^\bot , \Delta } } |
1176 |
%} |
1177 |
%\] |
1178 |
\item The structural step preceding a cut is a contraction: |
1179 |
\[ |
1180 |
\vlderivation{ |
1181 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{?\Gamma, \Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot} }{ |
1182 |
\vlin{\cntr}{}{ ?A,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{ ?A,?A,\Sigma } } |
1183 |
} |
1184 |
} |
1185 |
\quad\to\quad |
1186 |
\vlderivation{ |
1187 |
\vliq{\cntr}{}{ ?\Gamma,\Sigma }{ |
1188 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,?\Gamma,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot } }{ |
1189 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?A,?\Gamma,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot} }{ \vlhy{ ?A,?A,?\Delta,\Sigma } } |
1190 |
} |
1191 |
} |
1192 |
} |
1193 |
\] |
1194 |
%\item The structural step preceding a cut is a parallel contraction: |
1195 |
%\[ |
1196 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1197 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{?\Gamma,?\Delta, \Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot} }{ |
1198 |
%\vlin{}{}{ ?A,?\Delta,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{ ?A,?A,?\Delta,?\Delta,\Sigma } } |
1199 |
%} |
1200 |
%} |
1201 |
%\quad\to\quad |
1202 |
%\vlderivation{ |
1203 |
%\vlin{}{}{ ?\Gamma,?\Delta,\Sigma }{ |
1204 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,?\Gamma,?\Delta,?\Delta,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot } }{ |
1205 |
%\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?A,?\Gamma,?\Delta,?\Delta,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma,!A^\bot} }{ \vlhy{ ?A,?A,?\Delta,?\Delta,\Sigma } } |
1206 |
%} |
1207 |
%} |
1208 |
%} |
1209 |
%\] |
1210 |
\end{enumerate} |
1211 |
|
1212 |
\subsection{Key cases: logical steps} |
1213 |
Finally, once all cuts have been permuted maximally on both sides, we have the cases when the cut-formula is principal for a preceding logical step on both sides. We have three cases, one for every pair of connectives. |
1214 |
\begin{enumerate} |
1215 |
\item The cut-formula is multiplicative: |
1216 |
\[ |
1217 |
\vlderivation{ |
1218 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,\Sigma }{ |
1219 |
\vliin{\vlte}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,A\vlte B }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,A} }{ \vlhy{\Delta,B} } |
1220 |
}{ \vlin{\vlpa}{}{ \Sigma, A^\bot \vlpa B^\bot }{ \vlhy{\Sigma , A^\bot , B^\bot} } } |
1221 |
} |
1222 |
\quad\to\quad |
1223 |
\vlderivation{ |
1224 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta,\Sigma }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,A} }{ |
1225 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Delta,\Sigma,A^\bot }{ \vlhy{\Delta,B} }{ \vlhy{\Sigma , A^\bot,B^\bot } } |
1226 |
} |
1227 |
} |
1228 |
\] |
1229 |
\item The cut-formula is additive, |
1230 |
\[ |
1231 |
\vlderivation{ |
1232 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta }{ |
1233 |
\vliin{\vlan}{}{ \Gamma,A\vlan B }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,A} }{ \vlhy{\Gamma,B} } |
1234 |
}{ \vlin{\vlor}{}{ \Delta,A^\bot\vlor B^\bot }{ \vlhy{\Delta, A^\bot } } } |
1235 |
} |
1236 |
\quad\to\quad |
1237 |
\vliinf{\cut}{}{ \Gamma,\Delta }{ \Gamma,A }{ \Delta,A^\bot } |
1238 |
\] |
1239 |
where the case for the other $\vlor$-rule is symmetric. |
1240 |
\item The cut-formula is exponential. |
1241 |
\[ |
1242 |
\vlderivation{ |
1243 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,\Delta }{ |
1244 |
\vlin{!}{}{ ?\Gamma,!A }{ \vlhy{?\Gamma , A} } |
1245 |
}{ |
1246 |
\vlin{?}{}{ \Delta,?A^\bot }{ \vlhy{\Delta, A^\bot } } |
1247 |
} |
1248 |
} |
1249 |
\quad\to\quad |
1250 |
\vliinf{\cut}{}{ ?\Gamma,\Delta }{ ?\Gamma,A }{ \Delta,A^\bot } |
1251 |
\] |
1252 |
\item The cut-formula is quantified. |
1253 |
\[ |
1254 |
\vlderivation{ |
1255 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta}{ |
1256 |
\vlin{\forall}{}{\Gamma, \forall x. A(x)}{\vltr{\pi(a)}{\Gamma, A(a)}{\vlhy{\quad}}{\vlhy{}}{\vlhy{\quad}}} |
1257 |
}{ |
1258 |
\vlin{\exists}{}{\Delta, \exists x . \lnot{A}(x)}{\vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{A}(t)}} |
1259 |
} |
1260 |
} |
1261 |
\quad \to \quad |
1262 |
\vlderivation{ |
1263 |
\vliin{\cut}{}{\Gamma, \Delta}{ |
1264 |
\vltr{\pi(t)}{\Gamma, A(t)}{\vlhy{\quad}}{\vlhy{}}{\vlhy{\quad}} |
1265 |
}{\vlhy{\Delta, \lnot{A}(t)}} |
1266 |
} |
1267 |
\] |
1268 |
\end{enumerate} |
1269 |
|
1270 |
|
1271 |
\end{document} |